Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–22 | Cite as

Two notions of metaphysical modality

  • Antonella Mallozzi
S.I.: Ground, Essence, Modality

Abstract

The paper explores the project of an ambitious modal epistemology that attempts to combine the a priori methods of Chalmers’ 2D semantics with Kripke’s modal metaphysics. I argue that such a project is not viable. The ambitious modal epistemology involves an inconsistent triad composed of (1) Modal Monism, (2) Two-Dimensionalism, and what I call (3) “Metaphysical Kripkeanism”. I present the three theses and show how only two of those can be true at a time. There is a fundamental incompatibility between Chalmers’ Modal Rationalism and Kripke’s modal metaphysics. Specifically, Chalmers’ conceivability entails possibilities that a Kripkean rejects as genuinely metaphysical. However, three positive stances in modal epistemology emerge from the combinations that the triad allows. One of those offers a promising way forward for 2D modal epistemologies. But it comes with a cost, as it requires abandoning modal monism and reshaping the scope of what a priori conceivability can give us access to.

Keywords

Modal epistemology Modal rationalism Conceivability Kripke Chalmers A priori Two-dimensionalism 

References

  1. Beebee, H., & Sabbarton-Leary, N. (Eds.). (2010). The semantics and metaphysics of natural kinds. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Biggs, S., & Wilson, J. (2017). The a priority of abduction. Philosophical Studies, 174, 735–758.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bueno, O. & Shalkowski, S. (2018). Modal epistemology (New Problems of Philosophy). Routledge.Google Scholar
  4. Casullo, A. (2014). Essays on a priori knowledge and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Casullo, A. (2014). Modal empiricism: What is the problem?. In Oxford studies in epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Chalmers, D. (1999). Materialism and the metaphysics of modality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59, 473–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chalmers, D. (2002a). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–201). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Chalmers, D. (2002b). On sense and intension. Philosophical Perspectives, 16, 135–182.Google Scholar
  10. Chalmers, D. (2004) The foundations of two-dimensional semantics. In García-Carpintero & Maciá (2006), pp. 55–141.Google Scholar
  11. Chalmers, D. (2010). The character of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Chalmers, D. (2011). The nature of the epistemic space. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 60–107). Oxford: Clarendon University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Devitt, M. (2005). There is no a priori. In E. Sosa & M. Steup (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 105–115). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  14. Devitt, M. (2015). Should proper names still seem so problematic? In A. Bianchi (Ed.), On reference (pp. 108–43). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Fine, K. (2005). Necessity and non-existence. Modality and tense: Philosophical papers (pp. 321–354). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Fischer, B. & Leon, F., (Eds.) (2017). Modal epistemology after rationalism. Synthese Library.Google Scholar
  17. Goff, P., & Papineau, D. (2014). What Is wrong with strong necessities? Philosophical Studies, 167, 749–762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hale, B. (2013). Necessary beings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Hale, B. (forthcoming). Essence and definition by abstraction. In Mallozzi, A. (ed.) New directions in the epistemology of modality, special issue of Synthese. Google Scholar
  20. Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Kripke, S. (1971). Identity and necessity. In M. K. Munitz (Ed.), Identity and individuation (pp. 135–64). New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  23. Lowe, E. J. (2012). What is the source of our knowledge of modal truths. Mind, 121, 919–950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Papineau, D. (2007). Kripke’s proof is ad hominem not two-dimensional. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 475–494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Peacocke, C. (1999). Being known. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Priest, G. (2016). Thinking the impossible. Philosophical Studies, 173, 2649–2662.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Roca-Royes, S. (2011). Conceivability and De Re modal knowledge. Nous, 45, 22–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Salmon, N. (1981). Reference and essence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Salmon, N. (1986). Frege’s puzzle. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity. The unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Soames, S. (2005). Reference and description. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Strohminger, M. (2015). Perceptual knowledge of nonactual possibilities. Philosophical Perspectives, 29, 363–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Vaidya, A. (2006). The metaphysical foundation of logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35, 179–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Vaidya, A. (2008). Modal rationalism and modal monism. Erkenntnis, 68, 191–212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Vaidya, A. (2017a). Modal knowledge: Beyond rationalism and empiricism. In B. Fischer & F. Leon (Eds.), Modal epistemology after rationalism, synthese library (pp. 85–114).Google Scholar
  36. Vaidya, A. (2017b). The epistemology of modality. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/modality-epistemology/. Accessed 6 Oct 2017.
  37. Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Williamson, T. (2016a). Modal science. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46, 453–492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Williamson, T. (2016b). Knowing by imagining. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 113–123). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Worley, S. (2003). Conceivability. Possibility and Physicalism, Analysis, 63, 15–23.Google Scholar
  41. Yablo, S. (2006). No fools cold: Notes on illusions of possibility. In M. García-Carpintero & J. Maciá (Eds.), Two-dimensional semantics (pp. 327–346). Oxford: Clarendon University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.The Graduate Center - CUNYNew YorkUSA

Personalised recommendations