Skip to main content
Log in

The epistemological objection to modal primitivism

  • S.I.: New Directions in the Epistemology of Modality
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Modal primitivists hold that some modal truths are primitively true. They thus seem to face a special epistemological problem: how can primitive modal truths be known? The epistemological objection has not been adequately developed in the literature. I undertake to develop the objection, and then to argue that the best formulation of the epistemological objection targets all realists about modality, rather than the primitivist alone. Furthermore, the moves available to reductionists in response to the objection are also available to primitivists. I conclude by suggesting that extant theories of the epistemology of modality are not sensitive to the question of primitivism versus reductionism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term “possible world” is misleading—it’s not that some worlds are possible, and some are not possible. These worlds are simply “out there”. Lewis invokes possible worlds throughout his work, but the main source for his metaphysical views on possible worlds comes from Lewis (1986). Modal realism is not the only version of realism about possible worlds or modality, nor is it the only reductionist view. It would be better if it were called something like “concretism” about possible worlds (see Menzel 2017); however, since “modal realism” is the name by which this view is widely recognized and discussed in the literature, I will stick with the term. Defenders of versions of modal realism include Bricker (1996, 2001), Divers (2002) and McDaniel (2004).

  2. See Bueno and Shalkowski (2015), however, for an argument against theoretical utility as a truth-indicative feature of modal theories.

  3. For the original formulation of the distinction, see Quine (1951).

  4. See for instance Lewis’s (1986: pp. 150–157) objections to versions of ersatzism about possible worlds.

  5. Note that this not Lewis’s own main objection to primitivism.

  6. See for instance Cameron (2010), Sidelle (1989), Sider (2012), and Thomasson (2007, 2013).

  7. For a canonical statement of this view, see Grice (1961).

  8. See Clarke-Doane (2017), Liggins (2010) and Linnebo (2006) for discussions of the Benacerraf problem in the mathematical case; see also Benacerraf (1973) for the original formulation.

  9. See Clarke-Doane (2017: pp. 17–18) for examples.

  10. Strohminger (2015) argues that we can have perceptual knowledge of modal truths, so on her view, some cases of modal knowledge meet the causal condition. But her view is the exception; most deny that we can have perceptual knowledge of modal truths.

  11. Let a modal entity be an entity of any ontological category whose existence, instantiation, etc. has implications for modal space.

  12. Modalism is defended in deRosset (2014), Forbes (1989, 1992), Peacocke (1978, 2002), and the Postcript to Prior and Fine (1977). It is also defended in the service of an account of logical consequence in Bueno and Shalkowski (2009, 2013, 2015). If we allow modalism to also encompass views on which maximal states of affairs or world properties are primitively possible, then we may also include Adams (1974, 1981), Plantinga (1974, 1976), and Stalnaker (1976, 2012).

  13. See Jubien (2009), Lycan (1988) and Wang (2013).

  14. The following works include defenses (or at least suggestions) of dispositionalism: Borghini and Williams (2008), Contessa (2010), Ellis (2001), Jacobs (2010, 2011), Molnar (2003), Mumford (2004), Pruss (2002, 2011), and Vetter (2015).

  15. Primitivists about essence include Fine (1994, 1995), Lowe (1998, 2008a, b), and Mallozzi (Forthcoming). Note that the primitivist status of essentialism is controversial. McLeod (2001) appears to accept a modal primitivist theory that invokes essence, but Bueno and Shalkowski (2009, 2013) claim to remain neutral on which is the prior notion, essence or necessity.

  16. Defenders of dispositionalism do typically endorse modal entities—namely, the dispositional properties underlying the dispositions of objects. But the dispositionalist’s views on the nature of such properties also furnishes them with a reply to the epistemological objection. Dispositionality is a causal notion. If an object x has the disposition towards some manifestation M, then x has the causal potential to interact in certain ways with other objects, as specified in M. The dispositionalist’s response to the epistemological objection is that their modal entities are not causally inert; they are in fact individuated by their causes and effects.

  17. There is, of course, disagreement about the proper relata of causal relations—this claim may require reformulation.

  18. Lycan (1979: pp. 294–295) agrees with Richards.

  19. See Lewis (1986: p. 109).

  20. See Lewis (1986: pp. 110–112). It is worth noting that in this passage, Lewis seems to assume that it is sensitivity which is at issue in the Benacerraf problem. For discussion of how this might be problematic, see section 2.4 of Clarke-Doane (2017). Further discussion of how Lewis’s view fares with the epistemological objection appears in Stalnaker (1996).

  21. For discussions of formulations of the principle of recombination, see Bricker (1996, 2001), Divers and Melia (2002), Efird and Stoneham (2008), and Nolan (1996).

  22. Bueno and Shalkowski (2015) and Peacocke (1997, 1999) have separately defended primitivist epistemologies that seem equally available to the reductionist. So Lewis’s story is not the only one available.

  23. Versions of combinatorialist principles also appear in Eddon (2007), Maudlin (2007), Saucedo (2011), Schaffer (2003, 2010), and Sider (2005).

  24. See for instance Chalmers (2002). Note that a view on which there are analytic or constitutive relations between conceivability and possibility is unavailable to the realist about modality.

  25. A prominent defender of this position is Yablo (1993).

References

  • Adams, R. (1974). Theories of actuality. Noûs, 8, 211–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, R. (1981). Actualism and thisness. Synthese, 49, 3–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1989). A combinatorial theory of possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 661–679.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borghini, A., & Williams, N. (2008). A dispositional theory of possibility. Dialectica, 62(1), 21–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, P. (1996). Isolation and unification: The realist analysis of possible worlds. Philosophical Studies, 84, 225–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, P. (2001). Island universes and the analysis of modality. In G. Preyer & F. Siebelt (Eds.), Reality and humean supervenience: Essays on the philosophy of David Lewis (pp. 27–55). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. (2009). Modalism and logical pluralism. Mind, 118(470), 295–321.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. (2013). Logical constants: A modalist approach. Noûs, 47(1), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. (2015). Modalism and theoretical virtues: Toward an epistemology of modality. Philosophical Studies, 172, 671–689.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2010). On the source of necessity. In B. Hale & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic and epistemology (pp. 137–152). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–200). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke-Doane, J. (2017). What is the Benacerraf problem? In F. Pataut (Ed.), Truth, objects, infinity: New perspectives on the philosophy of Paul Benacerraf (pp. 17–43). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2010). Modal truthmakers and two varieties of actualism. Synthese, 174(3), 341–353.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M. J. (1972). The world is everything that is the case. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50(1), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • deRosset, L. (2014). Possible worlds for modal primitivists. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(1), 109–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Divers, J. (2002). Possible worlds. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Divers, J., & Melia, J. (2002). The analytic limit of genuine modal realism. Mind, 111(441), 15–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddon, M. (2007). Armstrong on quantities and resemblance. Philosophical Studies, 136(3), 385–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • Efird, D., & Stoneham, T. (2008). What is the principle of recombination? Dialectica, 62(4), 483–494.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1988). Realism, mathematics and modality. Philosophical Topics, 16(1), 57–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1995). Sense of essence. In W. Sinott-Armstrong (Ed.), Modality, morality, and belief: Essays in honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (pp. 53–73). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (1989). Languages of possibility: An essay in philosophical logic. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (1992). Melia on modalism. Philosophical Studies, 68(1), 57–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 35, 121–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. (2010). A powers theory of modality. Philosophical Studies, 151(2), 227–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. (2011). Powerful qualities, not pure powers. The Monist, 94(1), 81–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jubien, M. (2009). Possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2010). Epistemological objections to platonism. Philosophy Compass, 5(1), 67–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2006). Epistemological challenges to mathematical platonism. Philosophical Studies, 129(3), 545–574.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (1998). Possibility of metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2008a). Essentialism, metaphysical realism, and the errors of conceptualism. Philosophia Scientiae, 12, 9–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2008b). Two notions of being: Entity and essence. In R. Le Poidevin & A. McGonigal (Eds.), Being: Developments in contemporary metaphysics (pp. 23–48). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1979). The trouble with possible worlds. In M. Loux (Ed.), The possible and the actual: Readings in the metaphysics of modality (pp. 274–316). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1988). Review of David Lewis, ‘On the plurality of worlds’. The Journal of Philosophy, 85(1), 42–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacBride, F. (1999). Could armstrong have been a universal? Mind, 108(431), 471–501.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallozzi, A. (Forthcoming). Putting modal metaphysics first. Synthese.

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). Suggestions from physics for deep metaphysics. In T. Maudlin (Ed.), The metaphysics within physics (pp. 78–103). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDaniel, K. (2004). Modal realism with overlap. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82(1), 137–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLeod, S. (2001). Modality and anti-metaphysics. Burlington: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C. (2017). Possible worlds. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/possible-worlds/. Accessed 17 Sept 2018.

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (1996). Recombination unbound. Philosophical Studies, 84, 239–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1978). Necessity and truth theories. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 7(1), 473–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1997). Metaphysical necessity: Understanding, truth and epistemology. Mind, 106, 521–574.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1999). Being known. Oxford: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2002). Principles for possibilia. Noûs, 36(3), 486–508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1976). Actualism and possible worlds. Theoria, 42, 139–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A., & Fine, K. (1977). Worlds, times, and selves. Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pruss, A. (2002). The actual and the possible. In R. Gale (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to metaphysics (pp. 317–333). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pruss, A. (2011). Actuality, possibility, and worlds. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 2, 11–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1968). Propositional objects. Critica, 2(5), 3–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, T. (1975). The worlds of David Lewis. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 53(2), 105–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saucedo, R. (2011). Parthood and location. In K. Bennett & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 6, pp. 223–284). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2003). The problem of free mass: Must properties cluster? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(1), 125–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010). The internal relatedness of all things. Mind, 119(474), 341–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle, A. (1989). Necessity, essence, and individuation: A defense of conventionalism. Cornell: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2003). Reductive theories of modality. In M. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 180–208). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2005). Another look at Armstrong’s combinatorialism. Nous, 39, 680–696.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2012). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1976). Possible worlds. Noûs, 10, 65–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1996). On what possible worlds could not be. In A. Morton & S. Stich (Eds.), Benacerraf and his critics (pp. 103–119). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2012). Mere possibilities. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strohminger, M. (2015). Perceptual knowledge of nonactual possibilities. Philosophical Perspectives, 29(1), 363–375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2007). Modal normativism and the methods of metaphysics. Philosophical Topics, 35(1/2), 135–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2013). Norms and necessity. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 51(2), 143–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, B. (2015). Potentiality: From dispositions to modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, J. (2013). From combinatorialism to primitivism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(3), 535–554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivablity a guide to possiblity? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53(1), 1–42.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to the two referees and an audience at the 2018 Pacific APA.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jennifer Wang.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wang, J. The epistemological objection to modal primitivism. Synthese 198 (Suppl 8), 1887–1898 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01954-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01954-4

Keywords

Navigation