Skip to main content
Log in

Tolerance and the distributed sorites

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

On some accounts of vagueness, predicates like “is a heap” are tolerant. That is, their correct application tolerates sufficiently small changes in the objects to which they are applied. (So, according to tolerant views, if a given object is a heap, it will necessarily remain a heap after one grain of sand is removed.) Of course, such views face the sorites paradox, and various solutions have been proposed. One proposed solution involves banning repeated appeals to tolerance, while affirming tolerance in any individual case. (So, you may always remove one grain of sand safely, but you mustn’t make a habit of it.) In effect, this solution rejects the reasoning (rather than the premises) of the sorites argument. This paper discusses a thorny problem afflicting this approach to vagueness. In particular, it is shown that, on the foregoing view, whether an object is a heap will sometimes depend on factors extrinsic to that object, such as whether its components came from other heaps. More generally, the paper raises the issue of how to count heaps in a tolerance-friendly framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Fine (1975), Williamson (1994) and Sorensen (2001).

  2. Weiss (1976), Kamp (1981) and Raffman (1994).

  3. Dummett (1975), Kamp (1981), Fara (2000), Eklund (2005) and Gaifman (2010).

  4. Zardini (2008), Weber (2010) and Cobreros et al. (2012).

  5. Ziff (1974), Weiss (1976), Rosenberg (1978, see pp. 42–43) and Gaifman (2010). For a critical review of this approach, see Sorensen (1988 pp. 219–224).

  6. Gaifman uses “Sorites conditional” in place of “tolerance principle.”

  7. This supposition is purely presentational.

  8. In debates about ethics, examples with a similar structure have been used. See Parfit (2003, p. 383, fn. 16), Temkin (2012, pp. 440–445), Voorhoeve (2014, pp. 82–84) and Barnett (forthcoming).

  9. It should be noted that Gaifman’s (2010) contextualist view is safe from this problem. On his view, a vague predicate “loses its tolerance” in contexts like that posed by the staircase (see his p. 17). The challenge presented is most pressing for views that regard tolerance principles as true without qualification.

  10. For constructive feedback and suggestions, I would like to thank Anna Brinkerhoff, David Christensen, Jamie Dreier, Kelly Gaus, Yongming Han, Richard Heck, Han Li, Matthew Mandelkern, Josh Schechter, Brett Topey, Leo Yan and three anonymous referees at Synthese. Many thanks.

References

  • Barnett, Z. (forthcoming). No free lunch: The significance of Tiny contributions. Analysis.

  • Cobreros, P., Égré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012). Tolerant, classical, strict. The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41(2), 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1975). Wang’s paradox. Synthese, 30(3/4), 201–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eklund, M. (2005). What vagueness consists in. Philosophical Studies, 125, 27–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fara, D. G. (2000). Shifting sands: An interest-relative theory of vagueness. Philosophical Topics 28, 45–81 (Originally published under the name “Delia Graff”).

  • Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth, and logic. Synthese, 30(3/4), 265–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaifman, H. (2010). Vagueness, tolerance and contextual logic. Synthese, 174(1), 5–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. (1981). The paradox of the heap. In Münnich, U. (Ed.),  Aspects of philosophical logic (pp. 225–277) Dordrecht.

  • Parfit, D. (2003). Justifiability to each person. Ratio, 16, 368–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raffman, D. (1994). Vagueness without paradox. Philosophical Review, 103(1), 41–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, J. F. (1978). The practice of philosophy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (1988). Blindspots. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (2001). Vagueness and contradiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, L. (2012). Rethinking the good: Moral ideals and the nature of practical reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Voorhoeve, A. (2014). How should we aggregate competing claims? Ethics, 125, 64–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Z. (2010). A paraconsistent model of vagueness. Mind, 119(476), 1025–1045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, S. (1976). The sorites fallacy: What difference does a peanut make? Synthese, 33(1), 253–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zardini, E. (2008). A model of tolerance. Studia Logica, 90(3), 337–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ziff, P. (1974). The number of english sentences. Foundations of Language, 11(4), 519–532.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zach Barnett.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Barnett, Z. Tolerance and the distributed sorites. Synthese 196, 1071–1077 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1499-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1499-4

Keywords

Navigation