Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Constructivism, representation, and stability: path-dependence in public reason theories of justice

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Public reason theories are characterized by three conditions: constructivism, representation, and stability. Constructivism holds that justification does not rely on any antecedent moral or political values outside of the procedure of agreement. Representation holds that the reasons for the choice in the model must be rationally explicable to real agents outside the model. Stability holds that the principles chosen in the procedure should be stable upon reflection, especially in the face of diversity in a pluralistic society. Choice procedures that involve at least two-stages with different information, as Rawls’s theory does, will be path-dependent and not meet the condition of representation since it will not be globally coherent. Attempts to solve this problem without eliminating the segmentation of choice in the procedure will run afoul of constructivism or stability. This problem is instructive because it highlights how public reason theories must evolve in the face of increased concerns about diversity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout, I use “public reason” theories to also refer to many forms of contractualist, contractarian, and constructivist theories generally. It should be clear from the arguments below what theories these criticisms will apply to.

  2. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pushing me on this point.

  3. In this context, rationalizability means that the choice set can be understood as a maximal set of a binary ordering of the underlying set of options. This is a basic concept in the theory of rational choice, see: (Bossert et al. 2006).

  4. What Sen sometimes calls “property \(\upalpha \)” that \(\forall x \in A \subset B \rightarrow [x \in C(B)\rightarrow x \in C(A)]\) (1970, 1993, 1997). I will refer to this property as “contraction consistency.”

  5. What Sen sometimes calls “property \(\upbeta \),” that \( [\forall x,y \in C(A) \& A \subset B] \rightarrow [x \in C(B)\rightarrow y \in C(A)]\) (1970, pp. 7–10). I will refer to this property as “expansion consistency.”

References

  • Alexander, J., & Skyrms, B. (1999). Bargaining with neighbors: Is justice contagious? Journal of Philosophy, 96(11), 588–598.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, T., & Sengupta, K. (2006). Rational choice and von Neumann–Morgenstern’s stable set: The case of path-dependent procedures. Social Choice and Welfare, 27(3), 611–619. doi:10.1007/s00355-006-0147-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1998). Game theory and the social contract, vol. 2: Just playing. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (2005). Natural justice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert, W., Sprumont, Y., & Suzumura, K. (2006). Rationalizability of choice functions on general domains without full transitivity. Social Choice and Welfare, 27(3), 435–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert, W., & Suzumura, K. (2011). Rationality, external norms, and the epistemic value of menus. Social Choice and Welfare, 37(4), 729–741. doi:10.1007/s00355-011-0568-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. P. (2015). Diversity, tolerance, and the social contract. Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 14(4), 429–448.

  • Buchanan, J. (2000). The limits of liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan. The collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J., & Tullock, G. (1999). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. The collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • D’Agostino, F. (1996). Free public reason: Making it up as we go. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1976). The original position. In D. Norman (Ed.), Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls’ “a theory of justice”. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2013). The disorder of public reason: A critical study of Gerald Gaus’s the order of public reason. Ethics, 124(1), 141–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, D. (2011). Human nature and the limits (if any) of political philosophy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39(3), 207–237. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2011.01207.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, S. (2002). Congruence and the good of justice. In S. Freeman (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Rawls (pp. 277–315). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gaertner, W., & Xu, Y. (1999). On rationalizability of choice functions: A characterization of the median. Social Choice and Welfare, 16(4), 629–638. doi:10.1007/s003550050165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2011). The order of public reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2013). The turn to a political liberalism. In M. Jon & D. Reidy (Eds.), A companion to Rawls (pp. 233–250). Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2016). The tyranny of the ideal: Justice in a diverse society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1986). Morals by agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert, P. (2012). Comparative assessments of justice, political feasibility, and ideal theory. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 15(1), 39–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, N., & List, C. (2004). Framing as path dependence. Economics and Philosophy, 20(2), 253–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, A. (1788). Federalist no. 1. In G. W. Carey & J. McClellan (Eds.), The federalist, The Gideon Edition, (pp. 1–4). Liberty Fund.

  • Hardin, R. (1988). Morality within the limits of reason. Chicago: University Of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1975). Moral relativism defended. The Philosophical Review, 84(1), 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1996). The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D., & Raiffa, H. (1957). Games and decisions: Introduction and critical survey. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2012). Justice for earthlings: Essays in political philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. (2005). ‘Ideal theory’ as ideology. Hypatia, 20(3), 165–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2014). The scope of instrumental morality. Philosophical Studies, 167(2), 435–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C., Colyvan, M., Martini, C., Sillari, G., & Sprenger, J. (2014). Disagreement behind the veil of ignorance. Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 377–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (1987). Abstraction, idealization and ideology in ethics. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 22, 55–69. doi:10.1017/S0957042X00003667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1996). The common mind: An essay on psychology, society, and politics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2006). Can contract theory ground morality? In J. Dreier (Ed.), Contemporary debates in moral theory (pp. 77–96). Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R. (1973). Path independence, rationality, and social choice. Econometrica, 41(6), 1075–1091.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poproski, R. (2010). The rationalizability of two-step choices. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 39(6), 713–743. doi:10.1007/s10992-010-9148-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quong, J. (2010). Liberalism without perfection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1980). Kantian constructivism in moral theory. The Journal of Philosophy, 77(9), 515–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1996). Political liberalism. Paperback. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999a). A theory of justice (Revised ed.). Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999b). Distributive justice. In S. Freeman (Ed.), Collected papers (pp. 130–153). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999c). Kantian constructivism in moral theory. In S. Freeman (Ed.), Collected papers (pp. 303–358). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999d). The independence of moral theory. In S. Freeman (Ed.), Collected papers (pp. 286–302). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabl, A. (2012). Hume’s politics: Coordination and crisis in the “History of England”. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidtz, D. (2011). Nonideal theory: What it is and what it needs to be. Ethics, 121(4), 772–796.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1970). Collective choice and social welfare. San Francisco: Holden-Day Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1993). Internal consistency of choice. Econometrica, 61(3), 495–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1997). Maximization and the act of choice. Econometrica, 65(4), 745–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2006). What do we want from a theory of justice? The Journal of Philosophy, 103(5), 215–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A. J. (2010). Ideal and nonideal theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(1), 5–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1996). Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stemplowska, Z. (2008). What’s ideal about ideal theory? Social Theory and Practice, 34(3), 319–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thrasher, J., & Vallier, K. (2015). The fragility of consensus. European Journal of Philosophy, 23(4), 933–954.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211(4481), 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. The Journal of Business, 59(4), S251–S278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, L. (2009). On the apparent paradox of ideal theory. Journal of Political Philosophy, 17(3), 332–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, L. (2012). Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: A conceptual map. Philosophy Compass, 7(9), 654–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2013). Political political theory: An inaugural lecture. Journal of Political Philosophy, 21(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weithman, P. (2010). Why political liberalism? On John Rawls’s political turn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiens, D. (2012). Prescribing institutions without ideal theory. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20(1), 45–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Alexei Procyshyn, Hun Chung, Justin Bruner, Keith Hankins, Leif Wenar, Jerry Gaus, Brian Kogelmann, Chad van Schoelandt, Danny Shahar, and audiences at the University of New South Wales, the University of Canterbury, Seoul National University, The University of Utah, and the University of Arizona for helpful comments on earlier version of this paper and for discussion on the topic.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Thrasher.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thrasher, J. Constructivism, representation, and stability: path-dependence in public reason theories of justice. Synthese 196, 429–450 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1488-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1488-7

Keywords

Navigation