Abstract
This paper seeks to answer the following question: What is a minimal set of entities that form an ontology of the natural world, given our well-established physical theories? The proposal is that the following two axioms are sufficient to obtain such a minimalist ontology: (1) There are distance relations that individuate simple objects, namely matter points. (2) The matter points are permanent, with the distances between them changing. I sketch out how one can obtain our well-established physical theories on the basis of just these two axioms. The argument for minimalism in ontology then is that it yields all the explanations that one can reasonably demand in science and philosophy, while avoiding the drawbacks that come with a richer ontology.
This is a preview of subscription content,
to check access.Notes
Castaneda (1980, p. 106) uses the term “super-Humean world”, meaning a view that does not regard energy (or forces) as something that exists in the world; but there is no rejection of absolute space or natural intrinsic properties considered in Castaneda. I’m grateful to Gordon Belot for suggesting the term “Super-Humeanism” for this view of a relationalism that rejects intrinsic properties of the spatial relata.
References
Albert, D. Z. (2015). After physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Nino, Z. (2008). On the common structure of Bohmian mechanics and the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 353–389.
Barbour, J. B., & Bertotti, B. (1982). Mach’s principle and the structure of dynamical theories. Proceedings of the Royal Society A, 382, 295–306.
Bell, J. S. (1987). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Belot, G. (2011). Geometric possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Belot, G. (2012). Quantum states for primitive ontologists. A case study. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 67–83.
Bhogal, H., & Perry, Z. R. (2017). What the Humean should say about entanglement. Noûs, 51, 74–94.
Bigaj, T. (2015). Dissecting weak discernibility of quanta. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 50, 43–53.
Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Briceno, S., & Mumford, S. (2016). Relations all the way down? Against ontic structural realism. In A. Marmodoro & D. Yates (Eds.), The metaphysics of relations (pp. 198–217). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Callender, C. (2015). One world, one beable. Synthese, 192, 3153–3177.
Castaneda, H. (1980). Causes, energy and constant conjunctions. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause. Essays presented to Richard Taylor (pp. 81–108). Dordrecht: Reidel.
Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145, 1–34.
Colin, S., & Struyve, W. (2007). A Dirac sea pilot-wave model for quantum field theory. Journal of Physics A, 40, 7309–7341.
Deckert, D., Esfeld, M., & Oldofredi, A. (2016). A persistent particle ontology for QFT in terms of the Dirac sea. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. arXiv:1608.06141 [physics.hist-ph] (Forthcoming).
Dickson, M. (2000). Are there material objects in Bohm’s theory? Philosophy of Science, 67, 704–710.
Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Quantum physics without quantum philosophy. Berlin: Springer.
Esfeld, M. (1998). Holism and analytic philosophy. Mind, 107, 365–380.
Esfeld, M. (2004). Quantum entanglement and a metaphysics of relations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 35, 601–617.
Esfeld, M. (2014). Quantum Humeanism, or: Physicalism without properties. Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 453–470.
Esfeld, M., & Lam, V. (2011). Ontic structural realism as a metaphysics of objects. In A. Bokulich & P. Bokulich (Eds.), Scientific structuralism (pp. 143–159). Dordrecht: Springer.
Esfeld, M., Lazarovici, D., Hubert, M., & Dürr, D. (2014). The ontology of Bohmian mechanics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 773–796.
Esfeld, M., Lazarovici, D., Lam, V., & Hubert, M. (2017). The physics and metaphysics of primitive stuff. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68, 133–161.
Feynman, R. P. (1966). The development of the space-time view of quantum electrodynamics. Nobel Lecture, December 11, 1965. Science, 153, 699–708.
Field, H. H. (1985). Can we dispense with space-time?. In P. D. Asquith & P. Kitcher (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1984 Biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 2, pp. 33–90).
French, S. (2014). The structure of the world. Metaphysics and representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hall, N. (2009). Humean reductionism about laws of nature. Unpublished manuscript http://philpapers.org/rec/HALHRA.
Heil, J. (2012). The universe as we find it. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Huggett, N. (2006). The regularity account of relational spacetime. Mind, 115, 41–73.
Jackson, F. (1994). Armchair metaphysics. In J. O’Leary-Hawthorne & M. Michael (Eds.), Philosophy in mind (pp. 23–42). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Keränen, J. (2001). The identity problem for realist structuralism. Philosophia Mathematica, 9, 308–330.
Ladyman, J. (2007). On the identity and diversity of objects in a structure. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl 81, 1–22.
Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go. Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lange, M. (2002). An introduction to the philosophy of physics: locality, fields, energy and mass. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lange, M. (2013). Grounding, scientific explanation, and Humean laws. Philosophical Studies, 164, 255–261.
Leibniz, G. W. (1890). Die philosophischen Schriften von G. W. Leibniz. Band 7. Edited by C. I. Gerhardt. Berlin: Weidmannsche Verlagsbuchhandlung.
Leibniz, G. W. (2000). G. W. Leibniz and S. Clarke: Correspondence. Edited by Roger Ariew. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Lewis, D. (1986a). Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lewis, D. (1986b). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 412, 473–490.
Loewer, B. (2012). Two accounts of laws and time. Philosophical Studies, 160, 115–137.
Lowe, E. J. (2016). The are (probably) no relations. In A. Marmodoro & D. Yates (Eds.), The metaphysics of relations (pp. 100–112). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Marshall, D. (2015). Humean laws and explanation. Philosophical Studies, 172, 3145–3165.
Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Maudlin, T. (2010). Can the world be only wavefunction? In S. Saunders, J. Barrett, A. Kent, & D. Wallace (Eds.), Many worlds? Everett, quantum theory, and reality (pp. 121–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Maudlin, T. (2015). The universal and the local in quantum theory. Topoi, 34, 349–358.
McKenzie, K. (2014). Priority and particle physics: Ontic structural realism as a fundamentality thesis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 353–380.
Miller, E. (2014). Quantum entanglement, Bohmian mechanics, and Humean supervenience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 567–583.
Miller, E. (2015). Humean scientific explanation. Philosophical Studies, 172, 1311–1332.
Mumford, S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.
Pettit, P. (1993). The common mind. An essay on psychology, society, and politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Saunders, S. (2006). Are quantum particles objects? Analysis, 66, 52–63.
Schaffer, J. (2010a). The internal relatedness of all things. Mind, 119, 341–376.
Schaffer, J. (2010b). Monism: The priority of the whole. Philosophical Review, 119, 31–76.
Vassallo, A., & Esfeld, M. (2016). Leibnizian relationalism for general relativistic physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 55, 101–107.
Wheeler, J. A., & Feynman, R. P. (1945). Interaction with the absorber as the mechanism of radiation. Reviews of Modern Physics, 17, 157–181.
Acknowledgements
A first version of this paper was presented at the conference “New trends in the metaphysics of science” in Paris in December 2015. I’m grateful to the participants for their feedback, to Max Kistler for the invitation to submit the paper to this special issue, and to three anonymous referees for their helpful comments. The programme set out in this paper is worked out in the book A minimalist ontology of the natural world, co-authored by Michael Esfeld and Dirk-André Deckert, forthcoming with Routledge in autumn 2017. Apart from the many discussions with Dirk-André Deckert, the view expressed in this paper is influenced by the work with my collaborators Mario Hubert, Dustin Lazarovici, Andrea Oldofredi and Antonio Vassallo.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Esfeld, M. A proposal for a minimalist ontology. Synthese 197, 1889–1905 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1426-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1426-8