Skip to main content
Log in

Knowing-how, showing, and epistemic norms

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I consider the prospects for an epistemic norm which relates knowledge-how to showing in a way that parallels the knowledge norm of assertion. In the first part of the paper I show that this epistemic norm can be motivated by conversational evidence, and that it fits in with a plausible picture of the function of knowledge. In the second part of the paper I present a dilemma for this norm. If we understand showing in a broad sense as a general kind of skill teaching, then the norm faces counterexamples of teachers who know how to teach, but not to do. On the other hand, it we understand showing more narrowly as involving only teaching by doing the relevant activity, then the data which initially supported the norm can be explained away by more general connections between knowledge-how and intentional action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The knowledge-norm of assertion is formulated in several different ways: as an imperative or must claim (Williamson 2000: pp. 241–243), as a claim about appropriateness (Brown 2008a), or as a claim about permissibility (Turri 2011: p. 37). There is also debate about whether the norm should also encompass the sufficiency claim (Brown 2008a, b, 2010, 2012). I will not consider these issues since the counterexamples to the knowledge-norm of showing concern the necessity of know-how for appropriate showing, and will cause problems to any of these formulations.

  2. From this point on, I will use unqualified claims about permissibility to refer to epistemic permission.

  3. Although KNS is only significant if it is possible to show without having know-how. This is a point we will return to in Sect. 4.3.

  4. The fact that I focus on cases in which one person learns from another’s teaching should not distract us from the fact that we can also acquire know-how through imitation, practice, and simple trial and error. Since our focus will be on the norms on interpersonal teaching, giving a full account of the ways in which we can acquire know-how is beyond the scope of this paper. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

  5. These cases might either be due to an intention to mislead, or innocent error. Thinking about false instructions is made more complex by the fact that show+wh constructions appear to be factive in the sense that one cannot show how to V, without the demonstrated way being genuine (for parallel discussion of tell+wh see Karttunen (1978: p. 11; Vendler 1980: pp. 283–284), Holton (1997)). To avoid talk of apparent showing, I will assume that the show+wh construction is not factive. For the same reason, I will assume that ‘teach’ is not a success term meaning that giving false instructions about how to V counts as teaching.

  6. This explanation is of a kind with Searle’s explanation of indirect requests (Searle 1979; McGlynn 2014: p. 93).

  7. In what follows I will use capitalisation to refer to concepts.

  8. This is a generalisation of Fricker’s point that Craig’s view of KNOWS-THAT leads to KNA (Fricker 2015). A number of authors have also suggested that Craig’s account naturally fits with the knowledge norm for practical reasoning (Greco 2008, 2012; Hannon 2013; McKenna 2013, 2014).

  9. Can know-how ever be picked up from testimony? Poston (2015) is sceptical, but Hawley (2010) argues that it can.

  10. See also Reynolds (2002: pp. 158–159).

  11. On this distinction, see Williams (1973: p. 149) and Craig (1990: p. 19)

  12. This connection is suggested by Fricker (2015: pp. 74–84). Williamson also claims that the point of having a speech act governed by the knowledge-norm is to facilitate the pooling of knowledge (2000: pp. 266–269).

  13. One might think that the point of KNOWS is to help us pick out people who can be relied upon to do things for or with us. For allusions to this view of KNOWS-HOW, see Moore (1997, p. C8), Hawley (2011: pp. 287–290). Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

  14. In all of these norms the phrase w is a way to V is within the scope of the verb. The assumption that show+how is non-factive is also crucial here (see footnote 5).

  15. KNS* is really only one of a family of knowledge norms which claim that different kinds of non-practical knowledge about how to V is the norm on showing. KNS* is the most general of these norms, but there is space to develop a norm that claims that some specific kind of non-practical knowledge about how to V is the norm on showing. For example, one might think that knowledge-how can be broken down into a propositional knowledge component and a practical component, and that the propositional knowledge component is the norm on showing. It would lead us too far astray to consider every possible way to formulate a knowledge norm relating to showing, especially since the evidence considered in Sect. 2 points toward KNS, rather than any more complex knowledge norm. Thanks to anonymous reviewer for this point.

  16. As with the norms stated above, KNS* says that knowing is necessary for appropriate showing, but not that it is sufficient for appropriate showing. This means that it is compatible with KNS* that even when an agent has knowledge, their showing can be inappropriate, for some reason other than ignorance. For example, we might think as in the cases of assertion and action there are high-stakes showing cases, in which more than knowledge is required for appropriate showing (Brown 2008b: pp. 174–181, 2010: pp. 555–556). Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this point.

  17. The supporter of KNS* might argue that there is some other explanation for the inappropriateness of Jared’s showing (see footnote 16), but it is difficult to see what that explanation might be: Jared’s showing seems to be a paradigm case in which showing fails precisely because it does not meet the relevant epistemic standard. Jared’s case certainly seems rather different from the high-stakes cases in which knowledge is insufficient for assertion.

  18. Landsman (2014).

  19. HipBoneMusic (2016).

  20. Maine Suzuki School. (n.d.). Thanks to Matthew McGrath for pointing this passage out to me.

  21. In a piece about the role of non-disabled athletes in para-sports, Chuck Aoki relates that whilst he was playing for the US wheelchair rugby team, half of the coaches were non-disabled (Aoki 2013).

  22. Of the female artistic gymnasts currently profiled on the British Gymnastics webpage, 3 of 13 have male coaches. British Gymnastics (2017).

  23. This distinction suggests a general recipe for coming up with counterexamples to KNT. Whatever one thinks of the distinction between skill at doing and skill at teaching, take a case of someone who is skilled at teaching something but not at doing it, and ask whether that agent’s teaching is epistemically permissible. I take it that there be at least some cases in which this kind of teaching is permissible.

  24. For a similar case see Stanley (2011: p. 128).

  25. Here is another recipe for cases of generative teaching. If one thinks that knowledge-how can be undermined by Gettier-type luck (Stanley and Williamson 2001: p. 435; Poston 2009; Cath 2011; Carter and Pritchard 2013), then there will be cases in which someone lacks knowledge how due to the presence of luck, but would otherwise be as well-placed to teach as someone who did have know-how. Thanks to Jessica Brown for this point.

  26. Because this example goes through on both Intellectualist and Anti-Intellectualist theories I need not make any particular assumptions about what makes knowledge-how practical, in particular whether knowledge-how requires being able to act. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

  27. In the sense of having what Glick calls ‘internal’ ability (Glick 2012).

  28. I don’t want to suggest that all practical knowledge requires practice; only that some does (Hawley 2010: p. 401). There is a large body of empirical evidence stressing the importance of deliberate practice for skill acquisition. See Ericsson (2006) and Ford et al. (2015).

  29. Asserting ‘S knows how to V’ often implicates ‘S can teach you to V’, and denying it can plausibly generate the opposing implication.

  30. There are interesting variants of this case concerning the instruction of groups. A coach who has never played Rugby might instruct her team how to do a particular move—say, a Springbok Loop—without knowing how to do any of the sub-activities involved in that move. Thanks to Matthew McGrath for this suggestion.

  31. See Anscombe (1957: p. 89), Stanley and Williamson (2001: pp. 442–443), Gibbons (2001: pp. 597–598), Stanley (2011: pp. 185–190), Hornsby (2016).

  32. For example, NEC has trouble with luckily successful action (Setiya 2008, 2009, 2012), and seems to rule out the possibility of learning to do something by practicing doing it. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising these worries.

  33. Although it is tempting to think that NEC entails KND (albeit a trivial version of KND), this is not the lesson that I want to draw. Instead, my contention is that if NEC is true then KND cannot be a genuine norm.

  34. See (Habgood-Coote unpublished manuscript).

  35. On the face of it INT faces problems with intentions to learn. One might think that INT makes it impermissible to learn to V by practicing V-ing, and that it cannot explain cases in which one intends to V by first learning to V, then V-ing (see Setiya 2008: p. 406). These cases are tricky for the supporter of INT, but she does have moves to explain such cases (see Habgood-Coote unpublished manuscript). For example, one might think that someone who is learning to V cannot permissibly form the full intention to V, but that they can form the intention to try to V. Similarly, as Seitya suggests, one might think that someone who is intending to V by learning can only permissibly intend to learn how to V. Thanks to two anonymous reviewers for raising these worries.

  36. INT does not entail a pedagogical knowledge-how norm on teaching (requiring that one know how to teach in order to appropriately teach). Rather it entails a pedagogical knowledge-how norm on intending to teach. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

  37. One might offer a practical function for KNOWS-HOW and keep the pooling story about KNOWS-THAT. This view is unattractive because it loses a general explanation of the function of KNOWS.

  38. I take it that this dictum is a criticism, and not a descriptive claim.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aoki, C. (2013). Do able-bodied people belong in para-sport? Retrieved February 9, 2017, from https://www.paralympic.org/blog/chuck-aoki-do-able-bodied-people-belong-para-sport#!prettyPhoto.

  • Bach, K. (2008). Applying pragmatics to epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 18, 68–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic communication and speech acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beilock, S., Carr, T., MacMahon, C., & Starkes, L. (2002). When paying attention becomes counterproductive: Impact of divided versus skill-focused attention on novice and experienced performance of sensorimotor skills. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 8(1), 6–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beilock, S., & Gray, R. (2012). From attentional control to attentional spillover: A skill-level investigation of attention, movement, and performance outcomes. Human Movement Science, 31, 1473–1499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • British Gymnastics. (2017). Gynmast profiles. Retrieved September 2, 2017, from https://www.british-gymnastics.org/gymnast-profiles.

  • Brogaard, B. (2011). Knowledge-how: A unified account. In J. Bengson & M. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 136–160). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2008a). The knowledge norm for assertion. Philosophical Issues, 12, 89–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2008b). Subject-sensitive invariantism and the knowledge norm for practical reasoning. Noûs, 42(2), 167–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2010). Knowledge and assertion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 549–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2012). Assertion and practical reasoning: Common or divergent epistemic standards? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84, 123–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, T., & Carr, T. (1989). Automaticity in skill acquisition: Mechanisms for reducing interference in concurrent performance. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 15, 686–700.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brownstein, M. (2014). Rationalizing flow: Agency in skilled unreflective action. Philosophical Studies, 168(2), 545–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brownstein, M., & Michaelson, E. (2015). Doing without believing: Intellectualism, knowledge-how, and belief-attribution. Synthese Advance. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0888-9.

  • Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2014). Telling, showing and knowing: A unified theory of pedagogical norms. Analysis, 74, 16–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1981). Knowledge in practice. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18, 53–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A., & Pritchard, D. (2013). Knowledge how and epistemic luck. Noûs, 49(3), 440–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cath, Y. (2011). Knowing how without knowing that. In J. Bengson & M. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 113–135). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature: An essay in conceptual synthesis. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Knowledge, assertion, and context. Philosophical Review, 111, 167–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2006). Assertion, knowledge, and rational credibility. Philosophical Review, 115(4), 449–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ericsson, K. (2006). The influence of experience and deliberate practice on the development of superior expert practice. In K. Ericsson, N. Charness, P. Feltovich, & R. Hoffman (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance (pp. 683–704). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Flegal, K., & Anderson, M. (2008). Overthinking skilled motor performance: Or why those who teach can’t do. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 15(5), 927–932.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ford, P., Coughlan, E., Hodges, N., & Williams, A. (2015). Deliberate practice in sport. In J. Baker & D. Farrow (Eds.), Routledge handbook of sports expertise (pp. 347–362). Routledge: Abingdon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (2015). Know first, tell later. In D. Henderson & J. Greco (Eds.), Epistemic evaluation: Purposeful epistemology (pp. 46–86). Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons, J. (2001). Knowledge in action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 579–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, E. (2011). Two methodologies for evaluating intellectualism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 83(2), 398–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, E. (2012). Abilities and know-how attributions. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2008). What’s wrong with contextualism? Philosophical Quarterly, 58(232), 416–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2012). A (different) virtue epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habgood-Coote, J. (unpublished manuscript) Knowledge-how is the norm of intention.

  • Hannon, M. (2013). The practical origins of epistemic contextualism. Erkenntnis, 78(4), 899–919.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2003). Success and knowledge-how. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40, 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2010). Testimony and knowing how. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(4), 397–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2011). Knowing how and epistemic injustice. In J. Bengson & M. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 283–299). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J., & Stanley, J. (2008). Knowledge and action. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 571–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • HipBoneMusic. (2016). Bone2Pick: Julie Landsman Interview [online video]. Retrieved February 9, 2017, from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=SHuuo7SJ69M

  • Holton, R. (1997). Some telling examples: A reply to Tsohatzidis. Journal of Pragmatics, 28, 625–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1980). Actions. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2005). Semantic knowledge and practical knowledge. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 79(1), 107–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2016). Intending, knowing how, infinitives. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L. (1978). Syntax and semantics of questions. In H. Hiz (Ed.), Questions (pp. 165–210). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keele, S., & Summers, J. (1976). The structure of motor programs. In G. E. Stelmach (Ed.), Motor control: Issues and trends (pp. 109–142). New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, Jennifer. (2008). Learning from words: Testimony as a source of knowledge. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landsman, J. (2014). Carmine Caruso method: Introduction with Julie Landsman [online video]. Retrieved February 9, 2017, from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=xdSShjFHqDk.

  • Maine Suzuki School. (n.d.). Getting Started with Suzuki. Retrieved February 9, 2017, from https://mainesuzukiviolin.com/lessons/.

  • McGlynn, A. (2014). Knowledge first?. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, R. (2013). ‘Knowledge’ ascriptions. Social Roles and Semantics. Episteme, 10(4), 335–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, R. (2014). Normative scorekeeping. Synthese, 191(3), 607–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2016). Thought in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, A. (1997). Points of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2005). Against intellectualism. Analysis, 65, 278–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pelling, C. (2013). Assertion and safety. Synthese, 190(17), 3777–3796.

  • Poston, T. (2009). Know how to be Gettiered? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 743–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poston, T. (2015). Know how to transmit knowledge? Noûs Advance. doi:10.1111/nous.12125.

  • Reynolds, S. (2002). Testimony. Knowledge and Epistemic Goals, Philosophical Studies, 110, 139–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, S. (2008). Why we should prefer knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 32(1), 79–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosefeldt, T. (2004). Is knowing-how simply a case of knowing-that? Philosophical Investigations, 27(4), 370–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt, Ian. (2003). Savoir faire. Journal of Philosophy, 100(3), 158–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1971). Thinking and self-teaching. Journal of the Philosophy of Education, 5(2), 228, 216–228.

  • Ryle, G. (2009). Teaching and training. In Collected papers (Vol. 2, pp. 464–447). Abingdon: Routledge.

  • Searle, J. (1979). Indirect speech acts. Expression and meaning (pp. 30–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2008). Practical knowledge. Ethics, 118, 388–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2009). Practical knowledge revisited. Ethics, 1201, 128–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2012). Knowing how. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112(3), 285–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Small, W. (2014). The transmission of skill. Philosophical Topics, 42(1), 85–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2010). Prompting challenges. Analysis, 70, 456–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2011). The express knowledge account of assertion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89, 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2013). Knowledge and suberogatory assertion. Philosophical Studies, 167, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2014). You gotta believe. In C. Littlejohn & J. Turri (Eds.), Epistemic norms: New essays on action, belief, and assertion (pp. 193–198). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Z. (1980). Telling the facts. In J. Searle, F. Keifer, & M. Bierwisch (Eds.), Speech act theory and pragmatics (pp. 273–290). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, M. (2005). Must we know what we say? Philosophical Review, 114, 227–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1973). Deciding to Believe. Problems of the self: Philosophical papers 1956–1972 (pp. 136–151). Cambridge: CUP.

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Mark Bowker, Jessica Brown, Joshua Dever, Katherine Hawley, Matthew McGrath, Andrew Peet, Fenner Tanswell, Alexander Sandgren, Kieran Setiya, Caroline Toubourg, Brian Weatherson, and audiences at St Andrews and MIT. This research was supported by a UK Arts and Humanities Research Council Doctoral Scholarship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Habgood-Coote.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Habgood-Coote, J. Knowing-how, showing, and epistemic norms. Synthese 195, 3597–3620 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1389-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1389-9

Keywords

Navigation