Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The missing self in scientific psychiatry

  • S.I.: Psych&Phil
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Various traditions in mental health care, such as phenomenological, and existential and cognitive-behavioral psychotherapy, implicitly or explicitly acknowledge that a disruption of the self, or the person, or the agent (often using these three concepts synonymously) is among the common denominators of different mental disorders. They often emphasize the importance of understanding patients as reasonsresponsive, in their full mental health relevant complexity, if their mental disorder is to be treated successfully. The centrality of the concept of the self is not mirrored in the mainstream scientific approaches in psychiatry however; the self has rarely been considered as the object of scientific research, the empirical investigation of which might yield successful explanations of and interventions in mental disorders. Thus, even though self-related phenomena are clinically relevant in so far as they give important information about a mental disorder to the clinician and help the development of effective interventions, they are not considered among the scientifically relevant properties of mental disorders. Leaving the self-related phenomena out of the scientific research on mental disorders can be attributed to the presupposition that the self is not empirically tractable and its use will hinder psychiatry’s goal to be scientific. In this paper, taking issue with this, I argue the self is empirically tractable, and its use as a target of research will not hinder psychiatry’s scientific commitments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Tellingly, albeit after much contentious debate, DSM-5 removed the bereavement exclusion criterion from the depression description. This means if an individual displays the above-mentioned symptoms for a two-week period because she has lost a significant person in her life, she can still be diagnosed with depression (Wakefield 2015; Tekin 2015).

  2. There is disagreement on whether and precisely how Hempel’s work affected the DSM. DSM-III Task force chair Robert Spitzer denies such influence, whereas philosophers such as Joseph Parnas and Louis Sass emphasize it. In a review article, Kendler et al. discuss the influence of Hempel’s operationalism on the development of Feighner criteria by psychiatrists at Washington University in St. Louis. Most recently, Parnas and Bovet trace the emergence of operationalism in psychiatry to Hempel. However, Schaffner and Tabb address the complexities of the causal relationship between Hempel and the DSM by pointing out the later work of Hempel moves away from logical positivism and is more sympathetic to a Kuhnian approach. I do not want to overstate Hempel’s influence on the DSM, but insofar as his work represents the shared understanding of science at the time, it is important to engage with it to understand the underlying reasons for psychiatry’s choice to ignore the self in scientific contexts (Parnas and Bovet 2014; Schaffner and Tabb 2014; Fulford and Sartorius 2009).

  3. I want to make it clear that I am not trying to develop an understanding of the metaphysics of the self, a debate in philosophy with a long and complex history. I do not commit myself to developing a philosophical account of the self; rather, I argue for its instrumental value in psychiatry.

  4. The desire to include the self as a scientific target in psychiatry embraces pluralism in psychiatric research and other models of the self may also be promising. I will not discuss those here.

References

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1952). Diagnostic and statistical manual: Mental disorders (1st ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1980). Diagnostic and statistical manual: Mental disorders (3rd ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual: Mental disorders (5th ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Azrin, N. H., Donohue, B., Besalel, V. A., Kogan, E. S., & Acierno, R. (1994a). Youth drug abuse treatment: A controlled outcome study. Journal of Child and Adolescent Substance Abuse, 3(3), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Azrin, N. H., McMahon, P. T., Donahue, B., Besalel, V., Lapinski, K. J., Kogan, E., et al. (1994b). Behavioral therapy for drug abuse: A controlled treatment outcome study. Behavioral Research and Therapy, 32(8), 857–866.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailer-Jones, D. M. (1999). Tracing the development of models in the philosophy of science. In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian & P. Thagard (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery (pp. 23–40). New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers.

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, A. T. (1962). Reliability of psychiatric diagnoses: A critique of systematic studies. American Journal of Psychiatry, 119, 210–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman, P. W. (1938). Operational analysis. Philosophy of Science, 5, 114–131. (Reprinted in Bridgman 1955, 1–26).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, K. M., & Onken, L. S. (2005). Behavioral therapies for drug abuse. American Journal of Psychiatry, 162(8), 1452–1460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2009). Operationalism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/operationalism/.

  • Cooper, J. E., Kendell, R. E., Gurland, B. J., Sartorius, N., & Farkas, T. (1969). Cross-national study of diagnosis of the mental disorders: Some results from the first comparative investigation. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 10(Suppl), 21–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1971). Intentional systems. The Journal of Philosophy, 68(4), 87–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fidler, T. L., Clews, T. W., & Cunningham, C. L. (2006). Reestablishing an intragastric ethanol self-infusion model in rats. Alcoholism: Clinical and Experimental Research, 30, 414–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • First, M. B., Pincus, H. A., Levine, J. B., Williams, J. B. W., Ustun, B., & Peele, R. (2004). Clinical utility as a criterion for revising psychiatric diagnoses. American Journal of Psychiatry, 161, 946–954.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (2013a). The shame of addiction. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 120(4), 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (2013b). Identity and addiction: What alcoholic memoirs teach. In K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. Gipps, Graham, J. Sadler, G. Stanghellini & T. Thornton (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry (pp. 865–888). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2016). “Models in Science”, The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). E. N. Zalta (Ed.), forthcoming. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/models-science/.

  • Fulford, K. W. M., & Sartorius, N. (2009). The secret history of ICD and the hidden future of DSM. In M. Broome & L. Bortolotti (Eds.), Psychiatry as cognitive neuroscience: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 29–47). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 725–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Models and fictions in science. Philosophical Studies, 143, 101–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, G. (2013). The disordered mind: Philosophy of mind and mental illness (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1994/1961). Introduction to problems of taxonomy. In Zubin, J. (Ed.), Field studies in the mental disorders. New York: Grune and Stratton, pp. 3–22. (Reproduced in Sadler, J. Z., O. P. Wiggins, & M. A. Schwartz (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on psychiatric classification (pp. 315–331) Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.)

  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New York: H. Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jopling, D. (2000). Self-knowledge and the self. New York: Routledge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langeland, W., Draijer, N., & van den Brink, W. (2002). Trauma and dissociation in treatment-seeking alcoholics: Towards a resolution of inconsistent findings. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 43, 195–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcenko, M. O., Kemp, S. P., & Larson, N. C. (2000). Childhood experiences of abuse, later substance use, and parenting outcomes among low-income mothers. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry, 70, 316–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1988). Five kinds of self-knowledge. Philosophical Psychology, 1, 35–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nestler, E. (2013). Cellular basis of memory for addiction. Dialogues Clinical Neuroscience, 15(4), 431–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novalis, P., Rojcewicz, S., & Peele, R. (1993). Clinical manual of supportive therapy. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., & Bovet, P. (2014). Psychiatry made easy: Operationalism and some of its consequences. In Philosophical issues in psychiatry III, Chapter 11. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Robins, E., & Guze, S. B. (1970). Establishment of diagnostic validity in psychiatric illness: Its application to schizophrenia. American Journal of Psychiatry, 126(7), 983–987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z. (2005). Values and psychiatric diagnosis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K., & Tabb, K. (2014). Hempel as a critic of Bridgman’s operationalism: Lessons for psychiatry from the history of science (a response to Bovet and Parnas). In K. Kendler & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry III, Chapter 24. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Schwartz, M. A., & Wiggins, O. P. (1987a). Typifications: the first step for diagnosis in psychiatry. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 175, 65–77.

  • Schwartz, M. A., & Wiggins, O. P. (1987b). Diagnosis and ideal type: A contribution to psychiatric classification. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 28(4), 227–91.

  • Tekin, Ş. (2014). The missing self in Hacking’s looping effects. In H. Kincaid & J. A. Sullivan (Eds.), Classifying psychopathology: Mental kinds and natural kinds (pp. 227–256). MIT Press.

  • Tekin, Ş. (2015). Against hyponarrating grief: Incompatible research and treatment interests in the DSM-5. The DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical reflections on the psychiatric babel. In P. Singy & S. Demazeux (Eds.), History, philosophy and the theory of the life sciences Series (Vol. 10), Springer Press, pp. 179–197.

  • Tekin, Ş. (2011). Self-concept through the diagnostic looking glass: Narratives and mental disorder. Philosophical Psychology, 24(3), 357–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tekin, Ş. (2016). Are Mental Disorders Natural Kinds? A Plea for a New Approach to Intervention in Psychiatry. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 23(2), 147–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2014). The self as a system of multilevel interacting mechanisms. Philosophical Psychology, 27, 145–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1980). The foundations of intersubjectivity: Development of interpersonal and cooperative understanding in infants. In D. Olson (Ed.), The social foundations of language and thought: Essays in Honor of J.S. Bruner (pp. 316–342). New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsou, J. (2015). DSM-5 and psychiatry’s second revolution: Descriptive vs. theoretical approaches to psychiatric classification. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical reflections on the psychiatric babel. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (2015). The loss of grief: Science and pseudoscience in the debate over DSM-5’s elimination of the bereavement exclusion. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical reflections on the psychiatric babel. History, philosophy and the theory of the life sciences series. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, R., & Brown, J. (2013). Theory of addiction (2nd ed.). Chichester: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkes, K. (1988). Real people. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Owen Flanagan, George Graham, William Bechtel, Adele Abrahamsen, the audiences present at the University of Pittsburgh (2014), the Southern Society for Philosophy of Psychiatry (2016), and the two anonymous reviewers for their feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Şerife Tekin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tekin, Ş. The missing self in scientific psychiatry. Synthese 196, 2197–2215 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1324-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1324-0

Keywords

Navigation