Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 195, Issue 5, pp 2089–2112 | Cite as

Embodied cognition and temporally extended agency

  • Markus E. Schlosser
Article
  • 618 Downloads

Abstract

According to radical versions of embodied cognition, human cognition and agency should be explained without the ascription of representational mental states. According to a standard reply, accounts of embodied cognition can explain only instances of cognition and agency that are not “representation-hungry”. Two main types of such representation-hungry phenomena have been discussed: cognition about “the absent” and about “the abstract”. Proponents of representationalism have maintained that a satisfactory account of such phenomena requires the ascription of mental representations. Opponents have denied this. I will argue that there is another important representation-hungry phenomenon that has been overlooked in this debate: temporally extended planning agency. In particular, I will argue that it is very difficult to see how planning agency can be explained without the ascription of mental representations, even if we grant, for the sake of argument, that cognition about the absent and abstract can. We will see that this is a serious challenge for the radical as well as the more modest anti-representationalist versions of embodied cognition, and we will see that modest anti-representationalism is an unstable position.

Keywords

Mental representation Embodied cognition Anti-representationalism Agency Philosophy of cognitive science 

References

  1. Adams, F. (2010). Action theory meets embodied cognition. In A. Buckareff & J. Aguilar (Eds.), Causing human action: New perspectives on the causal theory of action (pp. 229–252). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  2. Austin, J. J., & Vancouver, J. B. (1996). Goal constructs in psychology: Structure, process, and content. Psychological Bulletin, 120, 338–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction. Artificial Intelligence, 72, 173–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bratman, M. E. (1987). Intention, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bratman, M. E. (2000). Reflection, planning, and temporally extended agency. Philosophical Review, 109, 35–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2012). Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 119, 119–145.Google Scholar
  8. Chemero, T. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101, 401–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Clarke, R. (2010). Skilled activity and the causal theory of action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 523–550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Clowes, R. W., & Mendonça, D. (2016). Representation redux: Is there still a useful role for representation to play in the context of embodied, dynamicist and situated theories of mind? New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 26–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. Reprinted in Davidson 1980 (pp. 3–20).Google Scholar
  14. Davidson, D. (1978). Intending. Reprinted in Davidson 1980 (pp. 83–102).Google Scholar
  15. Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  16. Degenaar, J., & Myin, E. (2014). Representation hunger revisited. Synthese, 191, 3639–3648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger’s being and time, division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  18. Dreyfus, H. L. (2002a). Intelligence without representation: Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Dreyfus, H. L. (2002b). Refocusing the question: Can there be skillful action without propositional representations or brain representations. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 413–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Abnormalities in the awareness and control of action. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 355, 1771–1788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8, 465–486.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Gallagher, S. (2008). Are minimal representations still representations? International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16, 351–369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Gollwitzer, P. M., & Sheeran, P. (2006). Implementation intentions and goal achievement: A meta-analysis of effects and processes. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 38i, 69–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
  27. Haugeland, J. (1991). Representational genera. In W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & D. Rumelhart (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 61–90). New Jersey: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  28. Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  29. Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2014). Neural representations not needed: No more pleas, please. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13, 241–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Huys, R., Daffertshofer, A., & Beek, P. J. (2004). The evolution of coordination during skill acquisition: The dynamical systems approach. In A. M. Williams, N. J. Hodges, & M. Scott (Eds.), Skill acquisition in sport: Research, theory and practice (pp. 351–373). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  31. Jeannerod, M. (1997). The cognitive neuroscience of action. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  32. Juarrero, A. (2010). Intentions as complex dynamical attractors. In J. H. Aguilar & A. A. Buckareff (Eds.), Causing human actions: New perspectives on the causal theory of action (pp. 253–276). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  33. Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78, 601–627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  35. Markman, A. B., & Dietrich, E. (2000). In defense of representation. Cognitive Psychology, 40, 138–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Mele, A. R. (2009). Effective intentions: The power of conscious will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Menary, R. A. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Menary, R. A. (2010). Introduction to the special issue on 4E cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 459–463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition, 107, 179–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Silberstein, M., & Chemero, A. (2011). Dynamics, agency and intentional action. Humana Mente, 15, 1–19.Google Scholar
  41. Sterelny, K. (2010). Minds: Extended or scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 465–481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 675–691.Google Scholar
  44. van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 92, 345–381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  46. Vygotsky, L. (1986). Thought and language (Newly Edited by A. Kozulin). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  47. Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  48. Wolpert, D. M., & Kawato, M. (1998). Multiple paired forward and inverse models for motor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1317–1329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.School of PhilosophyUniversity College DublinBelfield, Dublin 4Ireland

Personalised recommendations