Skip to main content
Log in

Prioritised ceteris paribus logic for counterfactual reasoning

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The semantics for counterfactuals due to David Lewis has been challenged by appealing to miracles. Miracles may skew a given similarity order in favour of those possible worlds which exhibit them. Lewis responded with a system of priorities that mitigates the significance of miracles when constructing similarity relations. We propose a prioritised ceteris paribus analysis of counterfactuals inspired by Lewis’ system of priorities. By analysing the couterfactuals with a ceteris paribus clause one forces out, in a natural manner, those possible worlds which do not satisfy the requirements of the clause, thus excluding miracles. If no world can satisfy the ceteris paribus clause in its entirety, then prioritisation is triggered to select worlds that maximise agreement on those things which are favoured most.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Schurz (2002) on comparative ceteris paribus laws.

  2. The choice of \(\varGamma \) finite is largely technical. We will mention some possibilities and difficulties regarding the case where the ceteris paribus set \(\varGamma \) may be infinite in Sect. 7.

  3. We redefine the language more precisely as Definition 6 in the appendix, particularly avoiding non-well-founded sets \(\varGamma \). For simplicity we work with the one now stated.

  4. Though the set \(\mathsf {Prop}\setminus (\mathsf {UD}(\varphi ) \cup \mathsf {UD}(\psi ))\) is an infinite set when \(\mathsf {Prop}\) is, it is not as ambitious as the previous infinite sets we’ve considered, because it is a co-finite set. Co-finite sets are a special cases of flexible sets as defined and axiomatised in Seligman and Girard (2011). To keep focus, we will stick with finite \(\mathsf {CP}\)-sets in this paper, and leave an exploration of the flexibility approach to infinite sets in conditional logic for future research.

  5. It could be that neither \(A_\varGamma ^\mathcal {M}(v,w) \unlhd A_\varGamma ^\mathcal {M}(u,w)\) nor \(A_\varGamma ^\mathcal {M}(u,w) \unlhd A_\varGamma ^\mathcal {M}(v,w)\), as \(\unlhd \) is a preorder.

  6. We provide an example of a prioritisation order that allows for incomparability in Sect. 5.2.2.

  7. In \([\varphi ,\varGamma ,\le ]\), we use \(\le \) instead of \(\unlhd \) to indicate that the modality is based on the specific ceteris prioritisation given by naïve counting. We will use notation in a similar fashion below.

References

  • Bennett, J. (1974). Review of Lewis (1973). The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 4, 381–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2001). Modal logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dalal, M. (1988). Investigations into a theory of knowledge base revision: preliminary report. Proceedings of the Seventh National Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 2, 475–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • del Cerro, L. F., & Herzig, A. (1994). Interference logic = conditional logic + frame axiom. International Journal of Intelligent Systems, 9(1), 119–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • del Cerro, L. F., & Herzig, A. (1996). Belief change and dependence. In Proceedings of the 6th conference on Theoretical aspects of rationality and knowledge (pp. 147–161). Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc.

  • Doyle, J., & Wellman, M. P. (1994). Representing preferences as ceteris paribus comparatives. Ann Arbor, 1001, 48109–482110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2001). Statistical mechanics and the asymmetry of counterfactual dependence. Philosophy of Science, 68(3), S313–S324.

  • Fine, K. (1975). Review of Lewis’ counterfactuals. Mind, 84, 451–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Girard, P., Triplett, M.A. (2015). Ceteris paribus logic in counterfactual reasoning. In Proceedings of TARK XV.

  • Hendricks, V. F. (2006). Mainstream and formal epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holliday, W.H. (2014). Epistemic closure and epistemic logic I: Relevant alternatives and subjunctivism. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(1), 1–62.

  • Katsuno, H., & Mendelzon, A. O. (1991). Propositional knowledge base revision and minimal change. Artificial Intelligence, 52(3), 263–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee Bowie, G. (1979). The similarity approach to counterfactuals: Some problems. Noûs, 13(4), 477–498.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13(4), 455–476.

  • McCall, S. (1984). Counterfactuals based on real possible worlds. Noûs, 18(3), 463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic: From if to is. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Proietti, C. (2009). Ceteris paribus modalities and the future contingents problem. Logics for Dynamics of Information and Preferences., 173(1), 304–325.

  • Proietti, C., & Sandu, G. (2010). Fitch’s paradox and ceteris paribus modalities. Synthese, 173(1), 75–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). Counterfactuals, causal independence and conceptual circularity. Analysis, 64(284), 299–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2002). Ceteris paribus laws: Classification and deconstruction. Erkenntnis (1975-), 57(3), 351–372.

  • Seligman, J., & Girard, P. (2011). Flexibility in ceteris paribus reasoning. The Australasian Journal of Logic, 10(0), 67–99.

  • Tooley, M. (2003). The Stalnaker-Lewis approach to counterfactuals. The Journal of philosophy, 100(7), 371–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J., Girard, P., & Roy, O. (2009). Everything else being equal: A modal logic for ceteris paribus preferences. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38(1), 83–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1963). The logic of preference. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman, R. (2006). The future similarity objection revisited. Synthese, 150(1), 57–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We wish to thank the participants at the Australasian Association of Logic and the Analysis, Randomness and Applications meetings held in New Zealand in 2014. A preliminary version of this paper was presented at TARK XV and we wish to thank the participants for helpful suggestions on improving the paper. We also wish to thank Sam Baron, Andrew Withy, Balder ten Cate and the anonymous referees for valuable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Girard.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Girard, P., Triplett, M.A. Prioritised ceteris paribus logic for counterfactual reasoning. Synthese 195, 1681–1703 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1296-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1296-5

Keywords

Navigation