Skip to main content
Log in

A pragmatist view of the metaphysics of entanglement

  • S.I. The Metaphysics of Entanglement
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Quantum entanglement is widely believed to be a feature of physical reality with undoubted (though debated) metaphysical implications. But Schrödinger introduced entanglement as a theoretical relation between representatives of the quantum states of two systems. Entanglement represents a physical relation only if quantum states are elements of physical reality. So arguments for metaphysical holism or nonseparability from entanglement rest on a questionable view of quantum theory. Assignment of entangled quantum states predicts experimentally confirmed violation of Bell inequalities. Can one use these experimental results to argue directly for metaphysical conclusions? No. Quantum theory itself gives us our best explanation of violations of Bell inequalities, with no superluminal causal influences and no metaphysical holism or nonseparability—but only if quantum states are understood as objective and relational, though prescriptive rather than ontic. Correct quantum state assignments are backed by true physical magnitude claims: but backing is not grounding. Quantum theory supports no general metaphysical holism or nonseparability; though a claim about a compound physical system may be significant and true while similar claims about its components are neither. Entanglement may well have have few, if any, first-order metaphysical implications. But the quantum theory of entanglement has much to teach the metaphysician about the roles of chance, causation, modality and explanation in the epistemic and practical concerns of a physically situated agent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. By this word choice he unconsciously anticipated the monogamy of (maximal) entanglement.

  2. Interestingly he also used the word ‘verheddert’ on the same page to describe the way a system’s \(\psi \)-function gets tangled up with that of an apparatus during a measurement. He uses only ‘Verschränkung’ and ‘verschränkt’ throughout the rest of the paper.

  3. Or even to its adequacy:

    Indubitably the situation described here is, in present quantum mechanics, a necessary and indispensable feature. The question arises, whether it is so in Nature too. I am not satisfied about there being sufficient experimental evidence for that. (Schrödinger 1936, p. 451)

    Entanglement is still a necessary and indubitable feature of quantum theory—a feature that has by now received exhaustive experimental confirmation.

  4. The concept is now regularly applied to states of two or more systems that have never interacted, and even retrospectively to systems that no longer exist (e.g. in entanglement-swapping scenarios, some of which include delayed choice). It has been generalized to apply to other kinds of representations of states, also in relativistic quantum mechanics and quantum field theory.

  5. As the example shows, a Hilbert space generally has multiple inequivalent decompositions as a tensor product of Hilbert spaces.

  6. Ghirardi et al. (2002), Ghirardi (2013), Ladyman et al. (2013) and Caulton (2014).

  7. See (Fine 1986, chap. 3).

  8. Einstein was right to consider Dirac, von Neumann and others following them “orthodox” in his sense because they accepted the descriptive completeness of the theory.

  9. Rigorously, they can never be localized at a point and the eigenstate-eigenvalue link cannot be applied to either of these states. Physicists commonly assume a vague but stronger principle inferring spatial location from a “suffficiently” localized spatial \(\psi \)-function. That is why I use the phrase “or something like it”. It is interesting to note that the entangled spatial state to which the authors of the EPR argument appealed did not require rigorous localization of component spatial states. But they did apply the eigenstate-eigenvalue link to states without regard for mathematical niceties!

  10. Indeed this interactive interpretation was what motivated the analysis of holism and nonseparability in my Healey (1991), not some more “orthodox” interpretation.

  11. Here are two instances among many.

    ...the state vector is only a shorthand expression of that part of our information concerning the past of the system which is relevant for predicting (as far as possible) the future behavior thereof. ...the laws of quantum mechanics only furnish probability connections between results of subsequent observations carried out on a system. (Wigner 1963, p.166).

    ...the quantum state of a Qbit or a collection of Qbits is not a property carried by those Qbits, but a way of concisely summarizing everything we know that has happened to them, to enable us to make statistical predictions about the information we might then be able to extract from them. (Mermin 2007, p. 109)

  12. Here I part company with self-styled quantum Bayesians who take an agent’s quantum state to describe her personal state of belief. In Sect. 4 of Healey (2012a) I contrast both their view and Rovelli’s relationism with the present view of quantum states as objective but relational.

  13. In the “paradox” of Wigner’s friend it is the absence of such channels that places Wigner (outside the laboratory) in a different agent situation from his friend before he joins him in the lab.

  14. Here is another way to see the problem. Fine (1982) showed that the CHSH (1969) inequalities express necessary and sufficient conditions for probability distributions of variable pairs generated by applying the Born rule to a state vector in a Hilbert space of 4 or more dimensions to equal marginals of a joint probability distribution over all canonical magnitude claims about it. Gisin’s theorem shows those inequalities are violated by any entangled state of such a system.

  15. Seevinck (2010) provides examples in a nice review of work relating the monogamy of entanglement to the shareability of non-classical correlations.

  16. Giustina et al. (2015) report a recent advance on seminal previous experiments to which they refer.

  17. For a fuller account see my Healey (2016). Note that both the sketch, Sect. 9.1, and much of Sect. 10 depend on the view of quantum states presented in Sect. 7 (see also Healey 2012a).

  18. See http://www.colorado.edu/physics/2000/bec/how_its_made.html for a more complete elementary description.

  19. This would happen most of the time in any realistic experiment, since detector efficiencies are usually well below 100 %.

  20. Correspondence with Ismael confirms this is indeed the kind of modal connection intended in Ismael and Schaffer (2016).

  21. I use the “tenseless present” rather than the more idiomatic future tense here for reasons that will soon become clear.

  22. See Ismael (2008). I have slightly altered her notation to avoid conflict with my own. Here ‘e’ ambiguously denotes both an event and the proposition that it occurs. Cr stands for credence: an agent’s degree of belief in a proposition, represented on a scale from 0 to 1 and required to conform to the standard axioms of probability.

  23. Friederich makes a similar point in Friederich (2015).

  24. Since he cannot predict the actual value of \(Ch_{q}(e_{A})\) following his hypothetical polarization measurement, he would have to decide on his best estimate of \(Ch_{q}(e_{A})\) in accordance with Ismael’s (2008) Ignorance Principle:

    Where you’re not sure about the chances, form a mixture of the chances assigned by different theories of chance with weights determined by your relative confidence in those theories.

  25. A unitary evolution \(\Phi ^{+}\Rightarrow \Xi ^{+}\) corresponding to a local interaction there would still yield \(Pr_{\Xi ^{+}}(H_{B})={\frac{1}{2}}\).

  26. Einstein’s formulation of a principle of local action also appeals to intervention:

    The following idea characterizes the relative independence of objects far apart in space (A and B): external influence on A has no immediate (“unmittelbar”) influence on B; this is known as the ‘principle of local action’ (Einstein 1948, pp. 321–322)

  27. For further details see my (Healey 2012a, b, 2013, 2015).

  28. As does Price (2011) who advocates subject naturalism as an alternative rather than a contribution to metaphysics as currently practised.

References

  • Beisbart, C., & Hartmann, S. (2011). Probabilities in physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1964). On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Physics, 1, 447–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1966). On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 38, 447–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (2004). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics (Revised ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1927). The quantum postulate and the recent development of atomic theory. Nature, 121, 580–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 48, 696–702.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1958). Unity of knowledge. Reprinted in The philosophical writings of Niels Bohr volume II. Woodbridge, Connecticut: Ox Bow Press.

  • Caulton, A. (2014) Physical entanglement in permutation–invariant quantum mechanics. arXiv:1409.0246v1 [quant-ph] 31 Aug.

  • Clauser, J. F., Holt, R. A., Horne, M. A., & Shimony, A. (1969). Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories. Physical Review Letters, 23, 880–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickson, M., & Clifton, R. (1998). Lorentz-invariance in modal interpretations. In D. Dieks & P. Vermaas (Eds.), The modal interpretation of quantum mechanics (pp. 9–48). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1930). The principles of quantum mechanics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (2015). Some puzzles and unresolved issues about quantum entanglement. Erkenntnis, 80, 303–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eberhard, P. (1978). Bell’s theorem and the different conceptions of locality. Il Nuovo Cimento B, 46, 392–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1948). Quanten-mechanik und Wirklichkeit. Dialectica, 2, 320–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1949). Autobiographical notes; Reply to Criticisms. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-scientist. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 47, 777–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1982). Joint distributions, quantum correlations, and commuting observables. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 23, 1306–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1986). The shaky game. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (2014). The Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen argument. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/qt-epr/.

  • Friederich, S. (2015). Rethinking local causality. Synthese, 192, 221–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G.-C. (2013). The parts and the whole. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 40–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G.-C., Marinatto, L., & Weber, T. (2002). Entanglement and properties of composite systems. Journal of Statistical Physics, 108, 49–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giustina, M., et al. (2015). Significant-loophole-free test of Bell’s theorem with entangled photons. Physical Review Letters, 115, 250401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gisin, N. (1991). Bell’s inequality holds for all non-product states. Physics Letters A, 154, 201–2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, A. M. (1957). Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space. Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics, 6, 885–893.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (1989). The philosophy of quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (1991). Holism and nonseparability. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 393–421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (1994). Nonseparable processes and causal explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 25, 337–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2009). Holism and nonseparabiity in physics. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/physics-holism/.

  • Healey, R. (2012). Quantum theory: A pragmatist approach. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 729–771.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2012). Quantum decoherence in a pragmatist view: Dispelling Feynman’s mystery. Foundations of Physics, 42, 1534–1555.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2013). Observation and quantum objectivity. Philosophy of Science, 80, 434–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2015). How quantum theory helps us explain. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66, 1–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2016). Local causality, probability and explanation. In M. Bell & S. Gao (Eds.), Quantum nonlocality and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henson, J. (2013). Non-separability does not relieve the problem of Bell’s theorem. Foundations of Physics, 43, 1008–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (1985). Einstein on locality and separability. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 16, 171–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holism, Howard D. (1989). Separability and the metaphysical implications of the Bell experiments. In J. Cushing & E. McMullin (Eds.), Philosophical consequences of quantum theory: Reflections on Bell’s theorem (pp. 224–253). Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2008). Raid! Dissolving the big, bad bug. Nous, 4, 292–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. & Schaffer, J. (2016). Quantum holism: Nonseparability as common ground. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1201-2.

  • Juffman, T., et al. (2009). Wave and particle in molecular interference lithography. Physical Review Letters, 103, 263601.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kochen, S., & Specker, E. P. (1967). The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics, 17, 59–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Linnebo, Ø., & Bigaj, T. (2013). Entanglement and non-factorizability. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 215–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy–Leblond, J.-M. (1990). In K. V. Laurikainen & J. Viiri (Eds.) Discussion Sections of the Symposium on the Foundations of Modern Physics 1990. University of Turku.

  • Leifer, M. (2014). Is the quantum state real?”. Quanta, 3, 67–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability, Volume II. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986). Causal explanation. In Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 214–240). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Maudlin, T. (2011). Quantum non-locality and relativity (3rd ed.). Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myrvold, W. (2001). Modal interpretations and relativity. Foundations of Physics, 32, 1773–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myrvold, W. (2003). Relativistic quantum becoming. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53, 475–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mermin, N. D. (2007). Quantum computer science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. The Popular Science Monthly, 12, 286–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1996). Time’s arrow and Archimedes’ point. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2011). Naturalism without mirrors. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2012). Causation, chance and the rational significance of supernatural evidence. Philosophical Review, 121, 483–538.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1935). Discussion of probability relations between separated systems. In Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society (Vol. 31, pp. 63–555).

  • Schrödinger, E. (1935). Die gegenwärtige Situation in der Quantenmechanik. In Die Naturwissenschaften 48, 807–812; 49, 823–8; 50, 844–849.

  • Schrödinger, E. (1936). Probability relations between separated systems. In Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society (Vol. 32, pp. 446–452).

  • Seevinck, M. (2010). Monogamy of correlations vs. monogamy of entanglement. Quantum Information Processing, 9, 273–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J. (1932). Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D., & Timpson, C. (2010). Quantum mechanics on spacetime I: Spacetime state realism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 697–727.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A., & Zurek, W. H. (Eds.). (1983). Quantum theory and measurement. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1963). The problem of measurement. American Journal of Physics, 31, 6–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper benefited from discussions with Jenann Ismael and David Glick and helpful suggestions from two reviewers. I thank the Yetadel Foundation for support during the time it was written.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Healey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Healey, R. A pragmatist view of the metaphysics of entanglement. Synthese 197, 4265–4302 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1204-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1204-z

Keywords

Navigation