Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 195, Issue 7, pp 2967–2983 | Cite as

In defense of hearing meanings

  • Berit BrogaardEmail author
Defeaters in Current Epistemology

Abstract

According to the inferential view of language comprehension, we hear a speaker’s utterance and infer what was said, drawing on our competence in the syntax and semantics of the language together with background information. On the alternative perceptual view, fluent speakers have a non-inferential capacity to perceive the content of speech. On this view, when we hear a speaker’s utterance, the experience confers some degree of justification on our beliefs about what was said in the absence of defeaters. So, in the absence of defeaters, we can come to know what was said merely on the basis of hearing the utterance. Several arguments have been offered against a pure perceptual view of language comprehension, among others, arguments pointing to its alleged difficulties accounting for homophones and the context-sensitivity of ordinary language. After responding to challenges to the perceptual view of language comprehension, I provide a new argument in favor of the perceptual view by looking closer at the dependence of the justificatory qualities of experience on the notion of a defeater as well as the perceptual nature of language learning and language processing.

Keywords

Ambiguity Cognitive penetration Cognitive phenomenology Language comprehension Perceptual learning Phenomenal contrast argument Phenomenal dogmatism Presentational phenomenology Polysemy Top-down influences 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Brendan Balcerak-Jackson, Ned Block, Anna Drożdżowicz, Casey O’Callaghan, Francois Recanati, Josh Weisberg and Wayne Wu for helpful discussion of these issues and to Elijah Chudnoff, Kathrin Glüer, Anandi Hattiangadi, Casey Landers, Luca Moretti, Peter Pagin, Tommaso Piazza, David Poston, Dag Westerståhl, audiences at Stockholm and Houston and two anonymous reviewers for this journal for helpful comments on a previous version of the paper.

References

  1. Bayne, T. (2009). Perception and the reach of phenomenal content. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 385–404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bergmann, M. (2013). Phenomenal conservatism and the dilemma for internalism. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and justification: New essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism (pp. 154–180). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Brogaard, B. (2013a). Do we perceive natural kind properties? Philosophical Studies, 162(1), 35–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Brogaard, B. (2013b). Phenomenal seemings and sensible dogmatism. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and justification: New essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism (pp. 270–289). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Brogaard, B. (in press). Perceptual appearances of personality. Philosophical Topics.Google Scholar
  6. Brogaard, B., & Chomanski, B. (2015). Cognitive penetrability and high-level properties in perception: Unrelated phenomena? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 96(2015), 469–486.Google Scholar
  7. Brogaard, B., & Gatzia, D. E. (2015). Is the auditory system cognitively penetrable? Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1166. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chandrasekaran, B., Skoe, E., & Kraus, N. (2013). An integrative model of subcortical auditory plasticity. Brain Topography. doi: 10.1007/s10548-013-0323-9.
  9. Chase, W. G., & Simon, H. A. (1973a). The mind’s eye in chess. In W. G. Chase (Ed.), Visual information processing (pp. 215–281). New York: Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Chase, W. G., & Simon, H. A. (1973b). Perception in chess. Cognitive Psychology, 4, 55–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Christianson, K., Luke, S. G., & Ferreira, F. (2010). Effects on plausibility on structural priming. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 36, 538–544.Google Scholar
  12. Chudnoff, E. (2013). Intuition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Chudnoff, E. (2014). Review of Tucker (eds.) Seemings and justification. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/48118-seemings-and-justificationnew-essays-on-dogmatism-and-phenomenal-conservatism/.
  14. Chudnoff, E. (forthcoming). Intuition, presentational phenomenology, and awareness of abstract objects. Florida Philosophical Review.Google Scholar
  15. Chudnoff, E. (2016). Moral perception: High level perception or low level intuition? In T. Breyer & C. Gutland (Eds.), Phenomenology of thinking (pp. 207–220). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  16. Chudnoff, E., & DiDomenico, D. (2015). The epistemic unity of perception. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 96(4), 535–549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Conee, E. (2013). Seeming evidence. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and justification: New essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism (pp. 52–70). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Davidson, D. (1973). Radical interpretation. Dialectica, 27. Reprinted in Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 125–140). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984.Google Scholar
  19. Ferreira, F., Bailey, K. G. D., & Ferraro, V. (2002). Good-enough representations in language comprehension. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 11, 11–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Fodor, J. (1983). Modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  21. Fricker, E. (2003). Understanding and knowledge of what is said. In A. Barber (Ed.), Epistemology of language (pp. 325–366). London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Glezer, L. S., Kim, J., Rule, J., Jiang, X., & Riesenhuber, M. (2015). Adding words to the brain’s visual dictionary: Novel word learning selectively sharpens orthographic representations in the VWFA. The Journal of Neuroscience, 35(12), 4965–4972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Ghijsen, H. (2015). Grounding perceptual dogmatism: What are perceptual seemings? The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(2), 196–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Gilbert, C. D., & Li, W. (2013). Top-down influences on visual processing. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 14, 351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Gobet, F., & Simon, H. A. (1996). Templates in chess memory: A mechanism for recalling several boards. Cognitive Psychology, 31, 1–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gobet, F., & Simon, H. A. (2000). Five seconds or sixty? Presentation time in expert memory. Cognitive Science, 24, 651–682.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Gordon, I. E. (2004). Theories of visual perception (3rd ed.). Hove: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
  28. Longworth, G. (2008). Linguistic understanding and knowledge. Nous, 42(1), 50–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Lotto, A., & Holt, L. L. (2011). Psychology of auditory perception. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 2(5), 479–489.Google Scholar
  30. Lyons, J. (2015). Seemings and justification. Analysis Reviews, 75(1), 153–164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Matlin, M. W. (2013). Cognition (8th ed.). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.Google Scholar
  32. McDowell, J. (1978). On ‘The Reality of the Past’. In C. Hookway & P. Pettit (Eds.), Action and interpretation (pp. 127–244). Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar
  33. McDowell, J. (1981). Anti-realism and the epistemology of understanding. In H. Parret & J. Bouveresse (Eds.), Meaning and understanding (pp. 225–248). Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  34. McLaughlin, B., Rossman, T., & McLeod, B. (1983). Second language learning: An information-processing perspective. Language Learning, 33(2), 135–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. O’Callaghan, C. (2011). Against hearing meanings. The Philosophical Quarterly, 61(245), 783–807.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Pettit, D. (2010). On the epistemology and psychology of speech comprehension. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 5(Meaning, Understanding and Knowledge), 1–43.Google Scholar
  37. Politzer, G., & Bonnefon, J.-F. (2006). Two varieties of conditionals and two kinds of defeaters help reveal two fundamental types of reasoning. Mind and Language, 21(4), 484–503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Pollock, J. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge. Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  39. Pollock, J. (1987). Defeasible reasons. Cognitive Science, 11(4), 481–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 341–423.Google Scholar
  41. Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Reiland, I. (2015a). On experiencing meanings. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(4), 481–492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Reiland, I. (2015b). Experience, seemings, and evidence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 96(4), 510–534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Siegel, S. (2005). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. Szabo Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 481–503). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Siegel, S. (2012). Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Noûs, 46(2), 201–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Stanley, J. (2005). Hornsby on the phenomenology of speech. The Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 79, 131–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Suga, N., Xiao, Z., Ma, X., & Ji, W. (2002). Plasticity and corticofugal modulation for hearing in adult animals. Neuron, 36(1), 9–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Swets, B., Desmet, T., Clifton, C, Jr., & Ferreira, F. (2008). Underspecification of syntactic ambiguities: Evidence from self-paced reading. Memory and Cognition, 36, 201–216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Tucker, C. (2010). Why open-minded people should endorse dogmatism. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 529–545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of MiamiCoral GablesUSA

Personalised recommendations