Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 194, Issue 8, pp 2949–2971 | Cite as

Inscrutability and visual objects

  • Ben Phillips
Article
  • 157 Downloads

Abstract

The thesis that the visual system represents objects has garnered empirical support from a variety of sources in recent decades. But what kinds of things qualify as “objects” in the relevant sense? Are they ordinary three-dimensional bodies? Are they the facing surfaces of three-dimensional bodies? I argue that there is no fact of the matter: what we have are equally acceptable ways of assigning extensions to the relevant visual states. The view I defend bears obvious similarities to Quine’s thesis that linguistic reference is inscrutable. Importantly, though, I argue that even if Quine was wrong about inscrutability as a thesis about language and thought, the case for the inscrutability of visual reference remains strong.

Keywords

Perception Inscrutability Visual objects Indeterminacy Visual reference Multiple-object tracking 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the following people for helpful input on various versions of this paper: Ryan DeChant, Uriah Kriegel, Jesse Prinz, Jake Quilty-Dunn, David Rosenthal, and three anonymous referees. I would also like to thank Laura Larocca for her help with the figures.

References

  1. Buckingham, G., Cant, J., & Goodale, M. (2009). Living in a material world: How visual cues to material properties affect the way that we lift objects and perceive their weight. Journal of Neurophysiology, 102, 3111–3118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Burge, T. (2009). Five theses on de re states and attitudes. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), The philosophy of David Kaplan (pp. 246–316). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Burge, T. (2011). Border crossings: Perceptual and post-perceptual object representation. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(3), 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bushnell, B., Harding, P., Kosai, Y., & Pasupathy, A. (2011). Partial occlusion modulates contour-based shape encoding in primate area V4. Journal of Neuroscience, 31, 4012–4024.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Carey, D. P., Harvey, M., & Milner, A. D. (1996). Visuomotor sensitivity for shape and orientation in a patient with visual form agnosia. Neuropsychologia, 34, 329–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clarke, T. (1965). Seeing surfaces and physical objects. In M. Black (Ed.), Philosophy in America (pp. 98–114). London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.Google Scholar
  9. DeChant, R., & Quilty-Dunn, J. (ms). Perceptual content, indeterminacy, and natural selection: Defending Quine against Burge.Google Scholar
  10. Desimone, R., & Duncan, J. (1995). Neural mechanisms of selective visual attention. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 18, 193–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Belief: Form, content and function (pp. 17–36). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Egly, R., Driver, J., & Rafal, R. D. (1994). Shifting visual attention between objects and locations: Evidence from normal and parietal lesion subjects. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 123, 161–177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Evans, G. (1975). Identity and predication. In Collected papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  15. Fodor, J. (1994). The elm and the expert. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. Fodor, J. (2007). Revenge of the given. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 105–116). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  17. Gates, G. (1996). The price of information. Synthese, 107(3), 325–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Howe, P. D., Cohen, M. A., Pinto, Y., & Horowitz, T. H. (2010). Distinguishing between parallel and serial accounts of multiple object tracking. Journal of Vision, 10(8), 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Jackson, F. (1977). Perception: A representative theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  20. James, T. W., Culham, J., Humphrey, G. K., Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2003). Ventral occipital lesions impair object recognition but not object-directed grasping: An fMRI study. Brain, 126, 2463–2475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Kastner, S., & Ungerleider, G. (2000). Mechanisms of visual attention in the human cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 23, 315–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kellman, P., & Spelke, E. S. (1983). Perception of partly occluded objects in infancy. Cognitive Psychology, 15, 483–524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Martin, M. G. F. (2002). Particular thoughts and singular thoughts. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Logic, thought and language (pp. 173–214). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Millikan, R. (2004). Varieties of meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  26. Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2006). The visual brain in action (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Nakayama, K., He, Z. J., & Shimojo, S. (1995). Visual surface representation: A critical link between lower-level and higher-level vision. In S. M. Kosslyn & D. N. Osherson (Eds.), An invitation to cognitive science (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  28. Nanay, B. (2010). Perception and imagination: Amodal perception as mental imagery. Philosophical Studies, 150, 239–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Neta, R. (2007). Contextualism and a puzzle about seeing. Philosophical Studies, 134(1), 53–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Pautz, A. (2013). Does phenomenology ground mental content? In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Phenomenal intentionality (pp. 194–234). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Peacocke, C. (2014). Perception, biology, action, and knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 477–484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Phillips, B. (2015). Contextualism about object-seeing. Philosophical Studies. doi: 10.1007/s11098-015-0619-6.
  33. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2001). Visual indexes, preconceptual objects, and situated vision. Cognition, 80(1/2), 127–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2003). Seeing and visualizing: It’s not what you think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  35. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2006). Some puzzling findings in multiple object tracking (MOT): II. Inhibition of moving nontargets. Visual Cognition, 14(2), 175–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2007). Things and places: How the mind connects with the world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  37. Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  38. Quine, W. V. O. (1969). From a logical point of view. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Rensink, R. A., & Enns, J. T. (1998). Early completion of occluded objects. Vision Research, 38, 2489–2505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Schenk, T., & McIntosh, R. D. (2010). Do we have independent visual streams for vision and action? Cognitive Neuroscience, 1, 52–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Scholl, B. J., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1999). Tracking multiple items through occlusion: Clues to visual objecthood. Cognitive Psychology, 38, 259–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Scholl, B., Pylyshyn, Z. W., & Feldman, J. (2001). What is a visual object? Evidence from target merging in multiple object tracking. Cognition, 80, 159–177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Searle, J. (1987). Indeterminacy, empiricism, and the first person. The Journal of Philosophy, 84(3), 123–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Spelke, E. (1990). Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science, 14, 29–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Sugita, Y. (1999). Grouping of image fragments in primary visual cortex. Nature, 401, 269–272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Tse, P. (1999). Volume completion. Cognitive Psychology, 39, 37–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. van Lier, R., & Gerbino, W. (2014). Perceptual completions. In J. Wagemans (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of perceptual organization. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  48. van Lier, R., & Wagemans, J. (1999). From images to objects: Global and local completions of self-occluded parts. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 25(6), 1721–1741.Google Scholar
  49. van Marle, K., & Scholl, B. (2003). Attentive tracking of objects and substances. Psychological Science, 14(5), 498–504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Wu, W. (2008). Visual attention, conceptual content, and doing it right. Mind, 117(468), 1003–1033.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.The Graduate CenterCity University of New YorkNew YorkUSA

Personalised recommendations