Synthese

, Volume 194, Issue 7, pp 2581–2594 | Cite as

Poincaré’s aesthetics of science

Article

Abstract

This paper offers a systematic analysis of Poincaré’s understanding of beauty in science. In particular, the paper examines the epistemic significance Poincaré attributes to aesthetic judgement by reconstructing and analysing his arguments on simplicity and unity in science. I offer a consistent reconstruction of Poincaré’s account and show that for Poincaré simplicity and unity are regulative principles, linked to the aim of science—that of achieving understanding of how phenomena relate. I show how Poincaré’s account of beauty in science can be incorporated within his wider philosophy of science.

Keywords

Aesthetic Values Simplicity Unity Henri Poincaré Scientific realism 

References

  1. Ben-Menahem, Y. (2006). Conventionalism: From Poincaré to Quine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Dirac, P. A. M. (1980). The excellence of Einstein’s theory of gravitation. In M. Goldsmith, A. Mackay, & J. Woudhuysen (Eds.), Einstein: The first hundred years (pp. 41–46). Oxford: Pergamon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Duhem, P. (1954[1906]). The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Feynman, R. (1967). The character of physical law: The 1964 messenger lectures. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Friedman, M. (1999). Reconsidering logical positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Gower, B. S. (2000). Cassirer, Schlick and Structural Realism: The philosophy of the exact sciences in the background to early logical empiricism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 8, 71–106.Google Scholar
  7. Heisenberg, W. (1971). Physics and beyond: Encounters and conversations. (A. J. Pomerans, Trans.). London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
  8. Ivanova, M. (2015). Conventionalism, structuralism and neo-Kantianism in Poincaré’s philosophy of science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52, 114–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Ivanova, M. (2013). Did Perrin’s experiments Convert Poincaré to scientific realism? HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 3(1), 1–19.Google Scholar
  10. Ivanova, M. (2010). Pierre Duhem’s good sense as a guide to theory choice. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 58–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgement (E. Matthews, Ed., P. Guyer & E. Matthews, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Livingston, P. (2009). Poincaré’s delicate sieve: On creativity and constraints in the arts. In Michael Krausz, Denis Dutton, & Karen Bardsley (Eds.), The idea of creativity (pp. 129–146). Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  14. Mach, E. (1984). The analysis of sensations and the relation of the physical to the psychical (C. M. Williams, Trans.). La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  15. Massimi, M. (2011). Structural realism: A neo-Kantian perspective. In P. Bokulich & A. Bokulich (Eds.), Scientific structuralism (Vol. 281, pp. 1–25). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  16. McAllister, J. (1996). Beauty and revolution in science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Morrison, M. (2008). Reduction, unity and the nature of science: Kant’s Legacy? In M. Massimi (Ed.), Kant and philosophy of science today (Vol. 63, pp. 37–62). Cambridge: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements.Google Scholar
  18. Poincaré, H. (1963[1913]). Mathematics and science: Last essays. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
  19. Poincaré, H. (2001 [1902, 1905, 1908]). Science and hypothesis. In Gould, S. (Ed.), The value of science: essential writings of Henri Poincaré. New York: Modern Library.Google Scholar
  20. Stump, D. (2007). Pierre Duhem’s virtue epistemology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 38, 149–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Stump, D. (1989). Henri Poincaré’s philosophy of science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 20, 335–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Todd, S. C. (2008). Unmasking the truth beneath the beauty: Why the supposed aesthetic judgements made in science may not be aesthetic at all. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22, 61–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Watson, J. D. (1968). The double helix: A personal account of the discovery of the structure of DNA. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.Google Scholar
  24. Worrall, J. (1996[1989]). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? In Papineau, D. (Ed.), The Philosophy of science (pp. 139–166). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Zahar, E. (2001). Poincaré’s philosophy: From conventionalism to phenomenology. New York: Open Court Publishing Company.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München, Fakultät für Philosophie, Wissenschaftstheorie und ReligionswissenschaftMunich Center for Mathematical PhilosophyMünchenGermany

Personalised recommendations