Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 194, Issue 8, pp 2695–2720 | Cite as

Negative Doxastic Voluntarism and the concept of belief

  • Hans Rott
S.I.: Doxastic Agency

Abstract

Pragmatists have argued that doxastic or epistemic norms do not apply to beliefs, but to changes of beliefs; thus not to the holding or not-holding, but to the acquisition or removal of beliefs. Doxastic voluntarism generally claims that humans (sometimes or usually) acquire beliefs in a deliberate and controlled way. This paper introduces Negative Doxastic Voluntarism according to which there is a fundamental asymmetry in belief change: (i) humans tend to acquire beliefs more or less automatically and unreflectively, but (ii) they tend to withdraw beliefs in a controlled and deliberate way. I first present a variety of philosophical, empirical and logical arguments for Negative Doxastic Voluntarism. Then I raise two objections against it. First, the apparent asymmetry may result from a confusion of belief with other doxastic attitudes like assumption, supposition, hypothesis or opinion. Second, the apparent asymmetry seems to vanish if we focus on doxastic states rather than just beliefs. Some rejoinders and their consequences for the vague concept of belief are sketched.

Keywords

Doxastic voluntarism Belief Belief state Belief change Suspension of disbelief 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I have been entertaining, with much sympathy, the idea of Negative Doxastic Voluntarism for 15 years, and I have been grateful to many people along the way. My more recent thanks go to Georg Brun, Eva-Maria Konrad, Tim Kraft, Andrea Kruse, Rik Peels, Jaroslav Peregrin, Vladimír Svoboda, Verena Wagner, Heinrich Wansing, Frank Zipfel, and the participants of the Bochum Workshop on “Doxastic Agency and Epistemic Responsibility” held in June 2014 for their friendly criticism of some of my intermediate attempts to come to grips with this topic. Last but not least, I am very grateful to three anonymous referees of this journal for numerous perceptive critical comments.

References

  1. Asp, E., Manzel, K., Koestner, B., Denburg, N. N., & Tranel, D. (2013). Benefit of the doubt: A new view of the role of the prefrontal cortex role in executive functioning and decision making. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 7, Article 86, 13 pp.Google Scholar
  2. Audi, R. (1999). Doxastic voluntarism and the ethics of belief. Facta Philosophica, 1(1), 87–109. (Reprinted in M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty: Essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue, Oxford: Oxford University Press 2001, pp. 93–111.).Google Scholar
  3. Audi, R. (2008). The ethics of belief: Doxastic self-control and intellectual virtue. Synthese, 161(3), 403–418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bain, A. (1859). The emotions and the will (3rd ed.). London: Longmans, Green and Co. 1875.Google Scholar
  5. Brewka, G. (1991). Belief revision in a framework for default reasoning. In A. Fuhrmann & M. Morreau (Eds.), The logic of theory change (Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, Vol. 465, pp. 206–222). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  6. Cohen, L. J. (1992). An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Coleridge, S. T. (1817). Biographia literaria (J. Shawcross, Ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press 1907. (Two volumes).Google Scholar
  8. Evans, J. S. B. T. (2008). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning: Judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychololgy, 59, 255–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Foley, R. (2009). Beliefs, degrees of belief, and the Lockean thesis. In F. Huber & C. Schmidt-Petri (Eds.), Degrees of belief (pp. 37–47). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux: Modeling the dynamics of epistemic states. Cambridge: Bradford Books, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Gendler, T. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gerrig, R. J. (1993). Experiencing narrative worlds: On the psychological activities of reading. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Gerrig, R. J., & Egidi, G. (2010). The Bushwhacked Piano and the bushwhacked reader: The willing construction of disbelief. Style, 44(1–2), 189–206.Google Scholar
  14. Gerrig, R. J., & Rapp, D. N. (2004). Psychological processes underlying literary impact. Poetics Today, 25(2), 265–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gilbert, D. T. (1991). How mental systems believe. American Psychologist, 46(2), 107–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Gilbert, D. T. (1993). The assent of man: Mental representation and the control of belief. In D. M. Wegner & J. W. Pennebaker (Eds.), Handbook of mental control (pp. 57–87). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  17. Grove, A. (1988). Two modellings for theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17(2), 157–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hansson, S. O. (1993). Reversing the Levi identity. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 22(6), 637–669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Hansson, S. O. (Ed.). (1997a). Non-prioritized belief revision. Stockholm: Thales. (Special issue of Theoria, 63(1–2), pp. 1–134).Google Scholar
  20. Hansson, S. O. (1997b). Semi-revision. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic, 7(1–2), 151–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Hansson, S. O. (2014). Logic of belief revision. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. (Winter 2014 Ed.)Google Scholar
  22. Hilpinen, R. (1980). Some epistemological interpretations of modal logic. In G. H. vonWright (Ed.), Logic and philosophy/logique et philosophie (pp. 19–29). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Humberstone, L. (2011). The connectives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  24. Hume, D. (1739–40). A treatise of human nature (P. H. Nidditch, Ed., 2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press 1978.Google Scholar
  25. James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology (Two volumes). New York: Henry Holt & Co.Google Scholar
  26. James, W. (1896). The will to believe. In F. Burkhardt, F. Bowers, & I. Skrupskelis (Eds.), The works of William James (Vol. 6, pp. 13–33). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1979.Google Scholar
  27. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
  28. Levi, I. (1991). The fixation of belief and its undoing: Changing beliefs through inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Levi, I. (1998). Pragmatism and change of view. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 24(Supplement 1), 177–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Levi, I. (2004). Mild contraction: Evaluating loss of information due to loss of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Lewis, D. (1975). Languages and language. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 7, p. 3–35). University ofMinnesota Press. (Reprinted in D. Lewis, Philosophical papers, Vol. 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press 1983, pp. 163–188.).Google Scholar
  32. Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement and justification. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Google Scholar
  33. Lycan, W. G. (2013). Phenomenal conservatism and the principle of credulity. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and justification: New essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism (pp. 293–305). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Mandelbaum, E. (2014). Thinking is believing. Inquiry, 57(1), 55–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Meinong, A. (1902). On assumptions (J. Heanue, Ed.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press 1983.Google Scholar
  36. Nietzsche, F. (1882). The gay science (W. Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Random House 1974.Google Scholar
  37. Nottelmann, N. (2007). Blameworthy belief: A study in epistemic deontologism. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  38. Peirce, C. S. (1877). The fixation of belief. In N. Houser, C. Kloesel, & The Peirce Edition Project (Eds.), The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings (1867–1893) (Vol. 1, pp. 109–123). Bloomington: Indiana University Press 1992. (Originally in Popular Science Monthly, 12, 1–15.).Google Scholar
  39. Price, H. H. (1969). Belief. London/New York: Allen and Unwin/Humanities Press. (Reprinted as Vol. 4 of the Collected works of H.H. Price, Bristol: Thoemmes 1996.).Google Scholar
  40. Price, H. H., & Braithwaite, R. B. (1964). Symposium: Half-belief. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 38, 149–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. S. (1978). The web of belief (2nd ed.). New York: Random House.Google Scholar
  42. Reid, T. (1764). Inquiry into the human mind (D. R. Brookes, Ed.). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. (Reprinted in Th. Reid: Philosophical Works, Eds. W. Hamilton & H. M. Bracken, Vol. 1, Hildesheim: Olms 1967, pp. 93–211.).Google Scholar
  43. Rott, H. (2001). Change, choice and inference: A study in belief revision and nonmonotonic reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Rott, H. (2008a). Belief revision. In J. Adler & L. Rips (Eds.), Reasoning: Studies of human inference and its foundations (pp. 514–534). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Rott, H. (2008b). Information structures in belief revision. In P. Adriaans & J. van Benthem (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science (Vol. 8, pp. 457–482)., Philosophy of information Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  46. Rott, H. (2009a). Degrees all the way down: Beliefs, non-beliefs and disbeliefs. In F. Huber & C. Schmidt-Petri (Eds.), Degrees of belief (pp. 301–339). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Rott, H. (2009b). Shifting priorities: Simple representations for twenty-seven iterated theory change operators. In D. Makinson, J. Malinowski, & H. Wansing (Eds.), Towards mathematical philosophy (pp. 269–296). Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Noûs, 36(2), 249–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgment and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91(4), 531–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Spinoza, B. (1677). Ethics. In E. Curley (Ed.), The collected works of Spinoza (Vol. 1, pp. 408–617). Princeton: Princeton University Press 1985.Google Scholar
  51. Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states. In W. Harper & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in decision, belief change, and statistics (pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Stenius, E. (1967). Mood and language-game. Synthese, 17(3), 254–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Stich, S. (1978). Beliefs and subdoxastic states. Philosophy of Science, 45(4), 499–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Swinburne, R. (1979). The existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  56. Wolterstorff, N. (1996). John Locke and the ethics of belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Yablo, S. (2014). Aboutness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of RegensburgRegensburgGermany

Personalised recommendations