Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 194, Issue 9, pp 3327–3346 | Cite as

A pragmatic, existentialist approach to the scientific realism debate

  • Curtis Forbes
S.I.: New Thinking about Scientific Realism

Abstract

It has become apparent that the debate between scientific realists and constructive empiricists has come to a stalemate. Neither view can reasonably claim to be the most rational philosophy of science, exclusively capable of making sense of all scientific activities. On one prominent analysis of the situation, whether we accept a realist or an anti-realist account of science actually seems to depend on which values we antecedently accept, rather than our commitment to “rationality” per se. Accordingly, several philosophers have attempted to argue in favour of scientific realism or constructive empiricism by showing that one set of values is exclusively best, for anyone and everyone, and that the downstream choice of the philosophy of science which best serves those values is therefore best, for anyone and everyone. These efforts, however, seem to have failed. In response, I suggest that philosophers of science should suspend the effort to determine which philosophy of science is best for everyone, and instead begin investigating which philosophy of science is best for specific (groups of) people, with specific values, in specific contexts. I illustrate how this might be done by briefly sketching a single case study from the history of science, which seems to show that different philosophies of science are better at motivating different forms of scientific practice.

Keywords

Scientific realism Constructive empiricism Scientific practice Philosophy of science Voluntarism Epistemology Epistemic stances 

References

  1. Arabatzis, T. (2006). Representing electrons: A biographical approach to theoretical entities. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Assis, A. K. T., Wolfschmidt, K. H., & Wiederkehr, G. (2011). Weber’s planetary model of the atom. Hamburg: Tredition Science.Google Scholar
  3. Buchwald, J. (1993). Electrodynamics in context: Object states, laboratory practice, and anti-romanticism. In D. Cahan (Ed.), Hermann von Helmholtz and the foundations of nineteenth-century science (pp. 334–373). Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  4. Buchwald, J. (1994). The creation of scientific effects. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cartwright, N. (2007). Why be hanged for even a lamb? In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas van Fraassen (pp. 32–45). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Chakravartty, A. (2004). Stance relativism: Empiricism versus metaphysics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 35, 173–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chakravartty, A. (2007a). A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chakravartty, A. (2007b). Six degrees of speculation: Metaphysics in empirical contexts. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen (pp. 183–208). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Chakravartty, A. (2011). A puzzle about voluntarism about rational epistemic stances. Synthese, 178, 37–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Fine, Arthur (1984a). ”The Natural Ontological Attitude” in Leplin (1984), pp. 83-107. Reprinted in Fine (1986a), pp. 112-135.Google Scholar
  11. Fine, A. (1984b). And not antirealism either. Noûs, 18(1), 51–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fine, A. (1986a). The shaky game: Einstein, realism, and the quantum theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  13. Fine, A. (1986b). Unnatural attitudes: Realist and instrumentalist attachments to science. Mind, 96, 149–179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Forbes, G. (1916). Memories of Sir David Gill, K.C.B, H.M. Astronomer (1879-1907) at the Cape of Good Hope. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
  15. Hendry, R. (2001). Are realism and instrumentalism methodologically indifferent? Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2001(3), S25–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hertz, H. (1962). Electric waves: Being researches on the propagation of electric action with finite velocity through space, 1892 (D. E. Jones, Trans.). New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
  17. Hesse, M. (1966). Models and analogies in science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  18. Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Kukla, A. (1998). Studies in scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
  21. Lipton, P. (2004). Epistemic options. Philosophical Studies, 121, 147–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Leplin, J. (1986). Methodological realism and scientific rationality. Philosophy of Science, 53, 31–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Maxwell, J. C. (1873). A treatise on electricity and magnetism. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  24. Meulders, M. (2010). Helmholtz: From enlightenment to neuroscience. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Monton, B. (2007). Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Morrison, M. (1992). A study in theory unification: The case of Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 23(1), 103–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Moulines, C. U. (1981). Hermann von Helmholtz: A physiological approach to the theory of knowledge. In H. N. Jahnke & M. Otte (Eds.), Epistemological and social problems of the sciences in the early nineteenth century (pp. 65–73). Boston: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Psillos, S. (2000). Agnostic empiricism versus scientific realism: Belief in truth matters. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 14(1), 57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. London: Barnes and Noble.Google Scholar
  30. Shapin, S., & Schaffer, S. (1985). Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Turner, R. S. (1977). Hermann von Helmholtz and the empiricist vision. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 13, 48–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Van Fraassen, B. (1991). Quantum mechanics: An empiricist view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Van Fraassen, B. (2000). The false hopes of traditional epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LX, 2, 253–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Van Fraassen, B. (2002). The empirical stance. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Van Fraassen, B. (2004). Science as representation: Flouting the criteria. Philosophy of Science, 71, 794–804.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Van Fraassen, B. (2005). Replies to discussion on the empirical stance. Philosophical Studies, 121, 171–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. von Helmholtz, H. (1871). Gustav Magnus in Memorandum: Address to the Leibniz Meeting of the Academy of Sciences, July 6, 1871 (H. von Helmholtz, Ed., Popular Lectures on Scientific Subjects, E. Atkinson, Trans.). London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
  40. Wise, M. N. (1981). German concepts of force, energy, and the electromagnetic ether, 1845–1880. In G. N. Cantor & M. J. S. Hodge (Eds.), Conceptions of ether: Studies in the history of ether theories, 1740–1900 (pp. 269–307). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Woodruff, A. E. (1962). Action at a distance in nineteenth century electrodynamics. Isis, 53(4), 439–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and TechnologyUniversity of TorontoTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations