Abstract
The question of how we actually arrive at our knowledge of others’ mental lives is lively debated, and some philosophers defend the idea that mentality is sometimes accessible to perception. In this paper, a distinction is introduced between “mind awareness” and “mental state awareness,” and it is argued that the former at least sometimes belongs to perceptual, rather than cognitive, processing.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
In a similar fashion, Johnson (2000, p. 22) remarks that “mental states, and the minds that possess them, are necessarily unobservable constructs that must be inferred.”
The original German passage says: “Man kann wirklich sagen: der beseelte Körper hat Schmerzen. Und ob ein Körper beseelt ist, das nimmt man durch die Sinne wahr.”
The focus of the paper is the perceptual awareness of others as being minded human beings, although I acknowledge that it would be helpful to enlighten the relationship between being in a mental state and being minded. For instance, some might want to grasp this issue in light of the determinate/determinable distinction and argue that being minded might just be something like the most determinable mental property had by a certain organism. Being minded could be just being in the most general kind of mental state that is entailed by the possession of any more specific mental state (e.g., beliefs, emotions, intentions, etc.). I thank an anonymous referee for pointing this possibility out to me.
While this is not the focus of this paper, one might wonder whether dreamless sleep and unconsciousness would constitute counterexamples to such a claim. I’m indebted to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.
This form of dehumanization is best exemplified in the context of interethnic antagonism. In extreme cases, animal or organism metaphors for ethnic out-groups are commonplace. Examples include the characterization of Jews in the Holocaust or Tutsis in Rwanda as vermin (Haslam 2006). In less extreme cases, out-group members are perceived as less capable of experiencing complex emotions such as nostalgia and compassion (Leyens et al. 2001; Demoulin et al. 2009).
There are, of course, also important differences. When we perceive a minded human being, we don’t just perceive animacy and attribute behavioral or dispositional aspects that we might attribute to dots on a screen. Perceiving a mind in others enables individuals to regard others as deserving moral consideration (Gray et al. 2007, 2012). Also, the literature on dehumanization confirms that failure to perceive minds in other people may aggravate prejudice and facilitate humiliation and torture (Harris and Fiske 2006, 2011; Haslam and Loughnan 2014; Viki et al. 2013).
Except in cases of abnormal development (Abell 2000; Rutherford et al. 2006), children at early ages interpret simple geometric shapes as intentional agents (Gergely 1995; Csibra 1999; Rochat 1997), and this is robust across individuals and consistent across a wide range of cultures (Morris and Peng 1994; Hashimoto 1966).
Put simply, the phenomenal character of experience E refers to “what it is like to consciously undergo” E.
This question is often formulated as a question about phenomenal or representational content (see Chalmers 2006).
While this is not the place to provide a full defense of this claim, one problem is that such approaches only allow an indirect analysis of the relevant contents, via informational states (see Siegel 2011, pp. 83–87).
Introspection appears to be the most natural method for settling this question, as most would agree that the phenomenal character of experience is accessible to introspection. But while introspection is helpful in getting us closer to answering the question about the contents of perceptual experience, it has specific limitations. It does not reveal with sufficient precision what we want to know about the contents of experience. If we think of introspection as a domain-general faculty, it might reveal what’s “on one’s mind,” for instance, that we’re having an experience of the high-level property “being a mailbox,” but it will fail to discern whether such experience is perceptual (visual) or post-perceptual (cognitive). Also, if introspection alone could reveal whether or not high-level properties can be presented in perceptual experience, then we would expect less disagreement about the correct answer. However, this is clearly not the case in the literature (see Siegel 2011, p. 80).
I take this first premise to be plausible, and I will not seek to provide additional support for it.
I thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out to me.
References
Abell, F., et al. (2000). Do triangles play tricks? Attribution of mental states to animated shapes in normal and abnormal development. Cognitive Development, 15, 1–16.
Adolphs, R. (2002). Recognizing emotion from facial expressions: Psychological and neurological mechanisms. Behavioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews, 1(1), 21–62.
Apperly, I. (2011). Mindreaders: The cognitive basis of theory of mind. Hove, UK: Psychology Press.
Bayne, T., & Montague, M. (Eds.). (2011). Cognitive phenomenology. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carruthers, P. (1996). Autism as mind-blindness: An elaboration and partial defence. In P. Carruthers & P. Smith (Eds.), Theories of theories of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2009). How we know our own minds: The relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121–138.
Carruthers, P. (2013). Mindreading in infancy. Mind and Language, 28(2), 141–172.
Carruthers, P. (2015). Perceiving mental states. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 498–507.
Chalmers, D. (2006). Perception and the fall from Eden. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 49–125). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Collins, J. A., & Olson, I. R. (2014). Knowledge is power: How conceptual knowledge transforms visual cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 1–18. doi:10.3758/s13423-013-0564-3.
Csibra, G., et al. (1999). Goal attribution without agency cues: The perception of ‘pure reason’ in infancy. Cognition, 72, 237–267.
Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Delk, J. L., & Fillenbaum, S. (1965). Differences in perceived color as a function of characteristic color. The American Journal of Psychology, 78(2), 290–293.
Demoulin, S., Cortes, B. P., Viki, T. G., Rodriguez, A. P., Rodriguez, R. T., Paladino, M. P., & Leyens, J. Ph. (2009). The role of in-group identification in infra-humanization. International Journal of Psychology, 44(1), 4–11.
Duddington, N. A. (1919). Our knowledge of other minds. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 19, 147–178.
Epley, N., & Waytz, A. (2010). Mind perception. In S. T. Fiske, et al. (Eds.), The handbook of social psychology (5th ed., pp. 498–541). New York: Wiley.
Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1990a). A reply to Churchland’s perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality. In J. Fodor (Ed.), A theory of content and other essays (pp. 253–263). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1990b). Observation reconsidered. In J. Fodor (Ed.), A theory of content and other essays (pp. 231–251). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gallagher, S. (2008). Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 535–543.
Gallagher, S., & Varga, S. (2014). Social constraints on the direct perception of emotions and intentions. Topoi, 33(1), 185–199.
Gao, T., McCarthy, G., & Scholl, B. J. (2010). The wolfpack effect: Perception of animacy irresistibly influences interactive behavior. Psychological Science, 21(12), 1845–1853.
Gao, T., Newman, G. E., & Scholl, B. J. (2009). The psychophysics of chasing: A case study in the perception of animacy. Cognitive Psychology, 59(2), 154–179.
Gao, T., Scholl, B. J., & McCarthy, G. (2012). Dissociating the detection of intentionality from animacy in the right posterior superior temporal sulcus. Journal of Neuroscience, 32(41), 14276–14280.
Gelman, R., Durgin, F., & Kaufman, L. (1995). Distinguishing between animates and inanimates: Not by motion alone. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 150–184). New York: Oxford University Press.
Gergely, G., et al. (1995). Taking the intentional stance at 12 months of age. Cognition, 56, 165–193.
Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goldman, A. (2013). Joint ventures: Mindreading, mirroring and embodied cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, thoughts and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (1994). The theory theory. In L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.), Domain specificity in cognition and culture (pp. 257–293). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Gordon, R. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind and Language, 1, 158–171.
Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2008). The sting of intentional pain. Psychological Science, 19, 1260–1262.
Gray, H. M., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2007). Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315, 619.
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind perception is the essence of morality. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2), 101–124.
Green, M. (2007). Self-expression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hackel, L. M., Looser, C. E., & Van Bavel, J. J. (2014). Group membership alters the threshold for mind perception: The role of social identity, collective identification, and intergroup threat. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 52, 15–23.
Hansen, T., Olkkonen, M., Walter, S., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2006). Memory modulates color appearance. Nature Neuroscience, 9(11), 1367–1368.
Harris, L., & Fiske, S. (2006). Dehumanizing the lowest of the low: Neuroimaging responses to extreme out-groups. Psychological Science, 17, 847–853.
Harris, L., & Fiske, S. (2011). Dehumanized perception: A psychological means to facilitate atrocities, torture, and genocide? Zeitschrift für Psychologie/Journal of Psychology, 219, 175–181.
Hashimoto, H. (1966). A phenomenal analysis of social perception. Journal of Child Development, 2, 3–26.
Haslam, N. (2006). Dehumanization: An integrative review. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 10, 252–264.
Haslam, N., & Loughnan, S. (2014). Dehumanization and infrahumanization. Annual Review of Psychology, 65, 399–423.
Haslam, N., Bain, P., Douge, L., Lee, M., & Bastian, B. (2005). More human than you: Attributing humanness to self and others. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89, 937–950.
Haslam, N., Kashima, Y., Loughnan, S., Shi, J., & Suitner, C. (2008). Subhuman, inhuman, and superhuman: Contrasting humans with nonhumans in three cultures. Social Cognition, 26, 248–258.
Heal, J. (1986). Replication and functionalism. In J. Butterfield (Ed.), Language, mind, and logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hugenberg, K., & Sacco, D. (2008). Social categorization and stereotyping: How social categorization biases person perception and face memory. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 2(2), 1052–1072.
Johnson, S. C. (2000). The recognition of mentalistic agents in infancy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 22–28.
Koldewyn, K., Hanus, P., & Balas, B. (2014). Visual adaptation of the perception of “life”: Animacy is a basic perceptual dimension of faces. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 21(4), 969–975.
Krebs, J. R., & Dawkins, R. (1984). Animal signals: Mind-reading and manipulation? In J. R. Krebs & N. Davies (Eds.), Behavioral ecology: An evolutionary approach (pp. 380–402). Oxford: Blackwell.
Lavelle, J. S. (2012). Theory-theory and the direct perception of mental states. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(2), 213–230.
Levin, T. D., & Banaji, M. R. (2006). Distortions in the perceived lightness of faces: The role of race categories. The Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135(4), 501–512.
Leyens, J Ph, Cortes, B., Demoulin, et al. (2003). Emotional prejudice, essentialism, and nationalism: The 2002 Tajfel lecture. European Journal of Social Psychology, 33, 703–717.
Leyens, J Ph, Paladino, M. P., Rodriguez, R. T., et al. (2000). The emotional side of prejudice: The attribution of secondary emotions to ingroups and outgroups. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 4, 186–197.
Leyens, J Ph, Rodriguez, A. P., Rodriguez, R. T., et al. (2001). Psychological essentialism and the differential attribution of uniquely human emotions to ingroups and outgroups. European Journal of Social Psychology, 31, 395–411.
Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., Sutton, R., & Spencer, B. (2013). Dehumanization and social class: Animality in stereotypes of “white trash,” “chavs,” and “bogans”. Social Psychology, 45(1), 54–61.
MacLin, O. H., & Malpass, R. S. (2001). Racial categorization of faces: The ambiguous race face effect. Psychology, Public Policy and Law, 7, 98–118.
MacLin, O. H., & Malpass, R. S. (2003). The ambiguous-race face illusion. Perception, 32(2), 249–252.
Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84, 24–62.
McNeill, W. (2012). On seeing that someone is angry. European Journal of Philosophy, 20, 575–597.
Morewedge, C. K., Preston, J., & Wegner, D. M. (2007). Timescale bias in the attribution of mind. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93(1), 1–11.
Morris, M. W., & Peng, K. (1994). Culture and cause: American and Chinese attributions for social and physical events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 949–971.
Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretense, self-awareness and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Olkkonen, M., Hansen, T., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2008). Color appearance of familiar objects: Effects of object shape, texture, and illumination changes. Journal of Vision, 8(5), 1–16.
Opfer, J. E. (2002). Identifying living and sentient kinds from dynamic information: The case of goal-directed versus aimless autonomous movement in conceptual change. Cognition, 86, 97–122.
O’Shea, J. (2012). The ‘theory theory’ of mind and the aims of sellars’ original myth of Jones. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11, 175–204.
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 341–423.
Reddy, V. (2008). How infants know minds. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rochat, M., et al. (1997). Young infants’ sensitivity to movement specifying social causality. Cognitive Development, 12, 537–561.
Rutherford, M. D. (2013). Evidence for specialized perception of animate motion. In M. D. Rutherford & V. A. Kuhlmeier (Eds.), Social perception: Detection and interpretation of animacy, agency, and intention (pp. 115–138). Cambridge: MIT Press.
Rutherford, M. D., Pennington, B. F., & Rogers, S. J. (2006). The perception of animacy in young children with autism. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 36, 983–992.
Santos, N. S., David, N., Bente, G., & Vogeley, K. (2008). Parametric induction of animacy experience. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(2), 425–437.
Scholl, B. J., & Gao, T. (2013). Perceiving animacy and intentionality: Visual processing or higher-level judgment? In M. D. Rutherford & V. A. Kuhlmeier (Eds.), Social perception: Detection and interpretation of animacy, agency, and intention. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Scholl, B. J., & Tremoulet, P. D. (2000). Perceptual causality and animacy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(8), 299–309.
Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. I, pp. 253–329). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 481–503). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Siegel, S. (2011). The contents of visual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Smith, J. (2010). Seeing other people. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 731–748.
Stokes, D. (2012). Perceiving and desiring: A new look at the cognitive penetrability of experience. Philosophical Studies, 158(3), 477–492.
Stokes, D. (2013). Cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophy Compass, 8(7), 646–663.
Stokes, D. (2015). Towards a consequentialist understanding of cognitive penetration. In A. Raftopoulos & J. Ziembekis (Eds.), Cognitive effects on perception: New philosophical perspectives. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198738916.003.0003.
Tremoulet, P. D., & Feldman, J. (2006). The influence of spatial context and the role of intentionality in the interpretation of animacy from motion. Perception and Psychophysics, 68(6), 1047–1058.
Vetter, P., & Newen, A. (2014). Varieties of cognitive penetration in visual perception. Consciousness & Cognition, 27, 62–75.
Viki, G., Osgood, D., & Phillips, S. (2013). Dehumanization and self-reported proclivity to torture prisoners of war. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 49, 325–328.
Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Wellman, H. (1992). The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1981). Zettel (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). In G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright (Eds.). Berkeley: University of California Press.
Witzel, C., Valkova, H., Hansen, T., & Gegenfurtner, K. (2011). Object knowledge modulates color appearance. Perception, 2(1), 13–49.
Yao, X., & Sloutsky, V. M. (2010). Selective attention and development of categorization: An eye tracking study. In S. Ohlsson & R. Catrambone (Eds.), Proceedings of the XXXII annual conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1980–1985). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Zahavi, D. (2008). Expression and empathy. In D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology reassessed (pp. 25–40). New York: Springer.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Varga, S. The case for mind perception. Synthese 194, 787–807 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0994-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0994-8
Keywords
- Mindreading
- The contents of perception
- Animacy