Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 193, Issue 9, pp 2987–3001 | Cite as

In defense of proper functionalism: cognitive science takes on Swampman

  • Kenny Boyce
  • Andrew Moon
Article

Abstract

According to proper functionalist theories of warrant, a belief is warranted only if it is formed by cognitive faculties that are properly functioning according to a good, truth-aimed design plan, one that is often thought to be specified either by intentional design or by natural selection. A formidable challenge to proper functionalist theories is the Swampman objection, according to which there are scenarios involving creatures who have warranted beliefs but whose cognitive faculties are not properly functioning, or are poorly designed, or are not aimed at truth. In this paper, we draw lessons from cognitive science in order to develop a novel argument for the conclusion that the Swampman objection fails against proper functionalist theories of warrant. Our argument not only shows that the underlying, central intuition motivating Swampman-like scenarios is false but also motivates proper function as a necessary condition for warrant, thereby lending support to the claim that any theory of knowledge that lacks a proper function requirement is false.

Keywords

Swampman Warrant Knowledge Proper functionalism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Sarah Boyce, Matthew Lee, Josh May, Matthew McGrath, Alvin Plantinga, Ted Poston, and Ernie Sosa for helpful correspondence and conversation concerning these matters. We are also thankful to the audience at the 2015 MidSouth Philosophy conference, including Matthew Frise, Derek Jones, Kevin McCain, Alex Radulescu, Josh Smart, and especially our commentator Nick Byrd.

References

  1. Baillargeon, R. (1987). Object permanence in 31/2 and 41/2-month-old infants. Developmental Psychology, 45, 655–664.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bergmann, M. (2006). Justification without awareness: A defense of epistemic externalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bergmann, M. (2013). Externalist justification and the role of seemings. Philosophical Studies, 166, 163–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bonjour, L. (2002). Internalism and externalism. In P. K. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 234–263). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Boyce, K., & Plantinga, A. (2012). Proper functionalism. In A. Cullison (Ed.), Companion to epistemology (pp. 124–140). London: Continuum Press.Google Scholar
  6. Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 661, 441–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Feldman, R. (1993). Proper functionalism. Nous, 27, 34–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Goldman, A. (2009). Replies to individual authors. In G. Schurz & M. Werning (Eds.), Reliable knowledge and social epistemology: Essays on the philosophy of Alvin Goldman and replies by Goldman (pp. 245–288). Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  9. Graham, P. (2012). Epistemic entitlement. Nous, 46, 449–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Graham, P. (2014). Warrant, functions, history. In A. Fairweather & O. Flanagan (Eds.), Naturalizing epistemic virtue (pp. 15–35). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Greco, J. (2000). Putting skeptics in their place. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Hespos, S. J., Gredeback, G., von Hofsten, C., & Spelke, E. S. (2009). Occlusion is hard: Comparing predictive reaching for visible and hidden objects in infants and adults. Cognitive Science, 33, 1483–1502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Huemer, M. (2013). Epistemological asymmetries between belief and experience. Philosophical Studies, 162, 741–748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Klein, P. (1996). Warrant, proper function, reliabilism. In J. Kvanvig (Eds.), Warrant in contemporary epistemology. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  15. Lyons, J. (2013). Should reliabilists be worried about demon worlds? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86, 1–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Markie, P. (2004). Nondoxastic perceptual experience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68, 530–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Markie, P. (2006). Epistemically appropriate perceptual belief. Nous, 40, 118–142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. McNabb, T. (forthcoming). Warranted religion: Answering objections to Alvin Plantinga’s epistemology. Religious Studies.Google Scholar
  19. Millikan, R. (1984). Naturalist reflections on knowledge. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 315–334.Google Scholar
  20. Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in the child. Oxford: Basic Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Plantinga, A. (1991). Warrant and designing agents: A reply to James Taylor. Philosophical Studies, 64, 203–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Plantinga, A. (1993a). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Plantinga, A. (1993b). Why we need proper function. Nous, 27, 66–82.Google Scholar
  24. Reid, T. (1764/1997). In D. Brookes (Ed.), An inquiry into the human mind on the principles of common sense. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Rosander, K., & von Hofsten, C. (2004). Infant’s emerging ability to represent occluded object motion. Cognition, 91, 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Sosa, E. (1993). Proper functionalism and virtue epistemology. Nous, 27, 51–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Spelke, E. (1994). Initial knowledge: Six suggestions. Cognition, 50, 431–445.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Spelke, E. S., & von Hofsten, C. (2001). Predictive reaching for occluded objects by 6-month-old infants. Journal of Cognition and Development, 2, 261–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Taylor, J. E. (1991). Plantinga’s proper functioning analysis of epistemic warrant. Philosophical Studies, 64, 185–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Tucker, C. (2011). Phenomenal conservativism and evidentialism in religious epistemology. In R. van Arragon & K. J. Clark (Eds.), Evidence and religious belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. von Hofsten, C., Kochukhova, O., & Rosander, K. (2007). Predictive tracking over occlusions by 4-month-old infants. Developmental Science, 10(5), 625–640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Wynn, K. (1992). Addition and subtraction by human infants. Nature, 358, 749–750.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Young, G. (2005). Ecological perception affords an explanation of object permanence. Philosophical Explorations: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action, 8, 189–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of MissouriColumbiaUSA
  2. 2.Rutgers UniversityNew BrunswickUSA

Personalised recommendations