Synthese

pp 1–18 | Cite as

Unconceived alternatives and conservatism in science: the impact of professionalization, peer-review, and Big Science

S.I. : Conceived Alternatives

Abstract

Scientific realists have suggested that changes in our scientific communities over the course of their history have rendered those communities progressively less vulnerable to the problem of unconcieved alternatives over time. I argue in response not only that the most fundamental historical transformations of the scientific enterprise have generated steadily mounting obstacles to revolutionary, transformative, or unorthodox scientific theorizing, but also that we have substantial independent evidence that the institutional apparatus of contemporary scientific inquiry fosters an exceedingly and increasingly theoretically conservative form of that inquiry. I conclude that contemporary scientific communities are actually more vulnerable to the problem of unconceived alternatives than their historical predecessors, and I briefly suggest how we might seek to pursue scientific inquiry in a less theoretically conservative way.

Keywords

Scientific Realism Instrumentalism Professionalization Peer-review Theoretical Conservatism Transformative research 

References

  1. Alvarez, L. W. (1987). Alvarez: The adventure of a physicist. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  2. Bement, A. L., Jr. (2007). Important Notice 130: Transformative Research, National Science Foundation, Office of the Director, published Sept. 24. Available from http://www.nsf.gov/pubs/2007/in130/in130.jsp. Accessed 16 July 2010.
  3. Bowler, P. J., & Morus, I. R. (2005). Making modern science: A historical survey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Braben, D. W. (2004). Pioneering research: A risk worth taking. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Interscience.Google Scholar
  5. Bush, V. (1945). Science: The Endless Frontier: A Report to the President on a Program for Postwar Scientific Research, 1960 reprint. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Office of Scientific Research and Development, National Science Foundation.Google Scholar
  6. Carter, L. J. (1979). A new and searching look at NSF. Science, 204, 1064–1065.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chubin, D. E., & Hackett, E. J. (1990). Peerless science: Peer review and U.S. science policy. New York: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
  8. Committee on Bridges to Independence: Identifying Opportunities for and Challenges to Fostering the Independence of Young Investigators in the Life Sciences, National Research Council (2005). Bridges to independence: Fostering the independence of new investigators in biomedical research. Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
  9. Daniels, George H. (1976). The process of professionalization in American science. In N. Reingold (Ed.), Science in America since 1820 (pp. 63–78). New York: Science History Publications.Google Scholar
  10. De Solla Price, D. (1963). Little science, big science. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Forber, P. (2008). Forever beyond our grasp? Biology and Philosophy, 23, 135–141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Foundation for the National Institutes of Health. (2013). The lurie prize in the biomedical sciences. Available from http://www.fnih.org/content/lurie-prize-biomedical-sciences. Accessed 19 Dec 2013.
  13. Galison, P., & Hevly, B. (1992). Big science: The growth of large-scale research. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2008). Recurrent transient underdetermination and the glass half full. Philosophical Studies, 137, 141–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hirsh, A. E. (2009). ‘Guest column: A new kind of big science’, New York Times (Opinionator: Exclusive Online Commentary from the Times), published Jan 13. Available from opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2009/01/13/guest-column-a-new-kind-of-big-science/. Accessed 16 July 2010.Google Scholar
  16. Horrobin, D. F. (1990). The philosophical basis of peer review and the suppression of innovation. Journal of the American Medical Association, 263, 1438–1441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Kaiser, J. (2014). NIH institute considers broad shift to ‘People’ Awards. Science, 345, 366–367. doi:10.1126/science/345.6195.366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kolata, G. (2009). ‘Playing it Safe in Cancer Research’, New York Times (Late Edition—Final ed.), published June 28. Retrieved July 16, 2010, from NewsBank on-line database (Access World News).Google Scholar
  19. Kuhn, T. S. (1996[1962]). The structure of scientific revolutions (3d ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  20. Lee, C., Sugimoto, C., Zhang, G., & Cronin, B. (2013). Bias in peer review. Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 64, 2–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Love, S. (2007). ‘To Break the Disease, Break the Mold’, New York Times (Late Edition—Final ed.), published April 1. Retrieved July 16, 2010, from NewsBank on-line database (Access World News).Google Scholar
  22. Luukkonen, T. (2012). Conservatism and risk-taking in peer review: Emerging ERC practices. Research Evaluation, 21, 48–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Mahoney, M. J. (1977). Publication prejudices: An experimental study of confirmatory bias in the peer review system. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 1, 161–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Mobley, A., Linder, S. K., Braeuer, R., Ellis, L. M., & Zwelling, L. (2013). A survey on data reproducibility in cancer research provides insights into our limited ability to translate findings from the laboratory to the clinic. PLOS One. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0063221.
  25. Muller, R. A. (1980). Innovation and scientific funding. Science, 209, 880–883.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Nathan, O., & Norden, H. (Eds.). (1960). Einstein on peace. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
  27. Resch, K. I., Ernst, E., & Garrow, J. (2000). A randomized controlled study of reviewer bias against an unconventional therapy. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 93, 164–7.Google Scholar
  28. Roy, R. (1985). Funding science: The real defects of peer review and an alternative to it. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 10, 73–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Rudwick, M. J. S. (1985). The Great Devonian Controversy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Shapin, S. (2008). The scientific life: A moral history of a late modern vocation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Shatz, D. (2004). Peer review: A critical inquiry. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  32. Stanford, P. K. (2001). Refusing the devil’s bargain: What kind of under determination should we take seriously? Philosophy of Science, 68, S1–S12.Google Scholar
  33. Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Stanford, P. K. (2015). Catastrophist vs. uniformitarian realism and a scientific realism debate that makes a difference. Philosophy of Science (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  35. Travis, G. D. L., & Collins, H. M. (1991). New light on old boys: Cognitive and institutional particularism in the peer review system. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 16, 322–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Wesseley, S. (1998). Peer review of grant applications: what do we know? The Lancet, 352, 301–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Wiener, N. (1948). A rebellious scientist after two years. Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 4, 338–339.Google Scholar
  38. Wiener, N. (1956). I am a mathematician: The later life of a prodigy. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.Google Scholar
  39. Zollman, K. J. S. (2007). The communication structure of epistemic communities. Philosophy of Science, 74, 574–587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Zollman, K. J. S. (2010). The epistemic benefit of transient diversity. Erkenntnis, 72, 17–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Logic and Philosophy of ScienceUniversity of California, IrvineIrvineUSA

Personalised recommendations