Skip to main content
Log in

On exhibiting representational validity

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We can distinguish two non-equivalent ways in which a natural language argument can be valid: it can be interpretationally or representationally valid. However, there is just one notion of classical first-order validity for formal languages: truth-preservation in all classical first-order models. To ease the tension, Baumgartner (Synthese 191:1349–1373, 2014) suggests that we should understand interpretational and representational validity as imposing different adequacy conditions on formalizations of natural language arguments. I argue against this proposal. To that end, I first show that Baumgartner’s definition of representational validity is extensionally inadequate. I present a number of natural language arguments that we pre-theoretically hold to be representationally valid, but are not representationally valid according to Baumgartner’s definition. I then point to two further untenable features of Baumgartner’s definitions: (i) according to Baumgartner’s definition of a representationally correct formalization, we cannot arrive at formalizations in a recursive way, and (ii) Baumgartner’s definition of representational validity is non-monotonic. I conclude that interpretational and representational validity cannot be understood as merely imposing different adequacy conditions on formalizations. If we want to capture our interpretational and representational intuitions, we need two different formal definitions of validity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Etchemendy (1990) introduced the distinction between interpretational and representational semantics in the context of his famous critique of Tarski’s definition of logical consequence (cf. Tarski 1956). For discussions of Etchemendy’s critique of Tarski, see for example Priest (1995), Ray (1996), Sher (1996), Gómez-Torrente (1996), Gómez-Torrente (1999), Gómez-Torrente (2009), Hanson (1997), Patterson (2008), but also Etchemendy (2008).

  2. This view has in turn been criticized by e.g. Goddu (2001), Read (2006); Bueno and Shalkowski (2009); Field (2009) and Vecsey (2010).

  3. From here on, all page numbers refer to Baumgartner 2014.

  4. Etchemendy (1990, Chap. 8) famously argued that there are also arguments that are interpretationally, but not representationally valid. The most prominent examples are sentences about the size of the world, as, e.g. “\(\exists \hbox {x}\exists \hbox {y} (\hbox {x}~\ne ~\hbox {y}\))”. Etchemendy claims that—if true—this sentence is trivially true under every interpretation of the non-logical constants, as it does not contain any. Thus, every argument with this sentence as its conclusion will be declared interpretationally valid. (If the sentence is false, every argument with the conclusion “\(\lnot [\exists \hbox {x}\exists \hbox {y}~(\hbox {x}~\ne ~\hbox {y}\))]” is said to be interpretationally valid.) I will not discuss these examples of Etchemendy here.

  5. To be precise, the interpretational definition of validity demands truth-preservation under all interpretations, rather than truth-preservation under all substitutions. The difference between the interpretational and the so-called substitutional definition of validity becomes important once we consider models with domains with unnamed objects. To avoid cumbersome formulations I will, however, follow Baumgartner in ignoring the difference between these two definitions whenever I can.

  6. Cf. Etchemendy 1990, pp. 24 and 63. For a similar argument used to introduce the notion of representational validity (though under a different label), see Beall and Restall 2006, pp. 37–38, and Sagi 2013.

  7. I use Greek upper case letters as parameters for natural language sentences (or sets thereof), and Greek lower case letters as parameters for formal language sentences (or sets of thereof).

  8. A notable exception is Halbach 2010.

  9. My formulation of (\(r-\mathrm{COR}\)) slightly differs from Baumgartner’s original definition as I make the reference to a correspondence scheme explicit (see the next paragraph for an explanation). For reasons of simplicity, I omit indexing models to \(\varphi \). (A model \({\mathfrak {M}}^{\varphi }\) provides an interpretation of the categorematic terms occurring in \(\varphi \).).

  10. More precisely, a model need not stand for a whole world, but only for a part of it, i.e. a model stands for a situation.

  11. \(t^{{\mathfrak {M}}}\)” stands for the interpretation of the constant \(t\) in the model \({\mathfrak {M}}\). To state this more precisely, let \({\mathfrak {M}}\) consist of the interpretation function \({\mathfrak {I}}\) and the non-empty domain D. We then have \(t^{{\mathfrak {M}}}\,= {\mathfrak {I}}(t)\) with \({\mathfrak {I}}(t)~\in \) D iff \(t\) is an individual constant, and \({\mathfrak {I}}(t)~\subseteq \hbox {D}^{n}\) iff \(t\) is an \(n\)-place relation constant.

  12. See p. 1361 for Baumgartner’s exact definition of \(i\)-correctness.

  13. More precisely, Baumgartner’s definition of \(i\)-correctness does not demand that the extensions be identical, but only that the actual extension of the natural language term corresponds to the extension of the term of the formal language interpreted in the model under consideration. For Baumgartner’s notion of correspondence, see p. 1360.

  14. Baumgartner stresses that the permissible reinterpretations need not only involve “English names and predicates that are listed in standard English dictionaries” as “the space of possible reinterpretations provided by the model-theoretic machinery far exceeds the expressive power of natural English” (p. 1361).

  15. To apply the definition of \(r\)-correctness to whole arguments, arguments must be understood as complex statements: the argument \(<\!\!\gamma , \psi \!\!>\) is understood as the material conditional \({\gamma }_{1}\,\wedge \,{\ldots }\wedge \, {\gamma }_{n}\,\rightarrow \psi (\hbox {with}\,\gamma = \{{\gamma }_{1,} {\ldots }, {\gamma }_{n}\)}). (See p. 1363)

  16. If your intuitions differ here, you will not accept (fa1) as an \(i\)-correct formalization of (a). As (fa1) is not FOL-valid anyway, this will have no consequences for the question whether or not argument (a) is interpretationally valid (see the definition of interpretational validity below). In the end, we are interested in the (interpretational) (in)validity of (a) and thus any discussion about the “correct intuitions” concerning the above reinterpretation is irrelevant.

  17. Argument (a) was introduced as a paradigm example of an argument that is intuitively judged to be representationally, though not interpretationally valid. As (fa2) is FOL-valid, argument (a) would be declared interpretationally valid by Baumgartner’s account in case one judges (fa2) to be \(i\)-correct (see the definition of interpretational validity below). We should therefore concede that the above reinterpretation is intuitively inadmissible.

  18. See Baumgartner (2014), p. 1371, for more on the notion of a minimally complex formalization.

  19. See Baumgartner (2014), p. 1369, for the exact definition of rr-correctness.

  20. Nevertheless, in a different context, Baumgartner & Lampert demand that “the expressions assigned to the categorematic parts of a formula by its realization [i.e. its correspondence scheme – the author] are logically independent and neither tautologous not contradictory.” (Baumgartner and Lampert 2008, p. 110).

  21. More precisely, proponents of the view that there are two informal notions of validity, interpretational and representational validity, will hold that there are two correlated notions of logical possibility and, therefore, of logical independence.

  22. The distinction between determinables and determinates is due to Johnson (1921), Chap. XI.

  23. If you do not think that humans are humans by necessity, choose your favorite example of a necessary property. Of course, this type of example only works under the assumption that there are objects that have certain properties by necessity (or, with obvious modifications, under the assumption that there are objects lacking certain properties by necessity).

  24. Baumgartner and Lampert (2008), p. 105, explicitly consider whether there is a more suitable formalism than first-order predicate logic to deal with statements involving color predicates. This would directly be relevant for argument (b).

  25. I here only refer to sentences which are Boolean connections of atomic sentences. I do not want to commit myself to the claim that we can formalize, e.g. molecular sentences involving atomic sentences in the scope of intensional operators in a recursive way (as e.g. in “Ben believes that Ann likes Cen.”).

  26. Of course, this assumes that the necessary adjustments concerning the identities and non-identities of the constants and variables are made. Although “Fa” might be an adequate formalization of “Daryl is a woman” and “Ga” might be an adequate formalization of “Russell is a man” considered individually, “\({Fa} \wedge {Ga}\)” is not an adequate formalization of “Daryl is a woman and Russell is a man.” Obviously, the case discussed in the main text is not of this kind.

  27. See especially Sainsbury (2001), Chap. 6, for a discussion of the claim that formalizations provide systematic representations of the truth conditions of natural language sentences. See also Epstein (1990) and Brun (2004) for more on systematic formalization. Halbach (2010), Chap. 3 and Chap. 7, also assumes that formalizations of molecular sentences are build up from formalizations of their atomic parts.

  28. See Peregrin and Svoboda 2013, pp. 2906–2907, for a similar example. They also use their example to show that IN does not allow us to arrive at formalizations in a recursive way.

  29. Needless to say, (g) seems to constitute a further counter-example to Baumgartner’s definition of representational validity: the natural language argument (g) is intuitively representationally valid, though there seems to be no \(r\)-correct and FOL-valid formalization of (g).

  30. Similarly, Peregrin and Svoboda 2013, p. 2909, claim that “[s]uch an exclusion [of inadmissible models – the author] brings us beyond the boundaries of logic [...].”

  31. For the sake of simplicity, I use a possibilist semantics where we have one domain of objects for all worlds.

  32. For the sake of simplicity, I spell out the semantics only for a language without variables.

  33. Of course, the role of the correspondence scheme has to be spelled out more carefully, but here is not the place to do so.

References

  • Baumgartner, M., & Lampert, T. (2008). Adequate formalization. Synthese, 164, 93–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M. (2014). Exhibiting interpretational and representational validity. Synthese, 191, 1349–1373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G., & Mönnich, U. (1989). Property theories. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (pp. 133–251). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C., & Restall, G. (2006). Logical pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brun, G. (2004). Die richtige formel. Philosophische probleme der logischen formalisierung. Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. (2009). Modalism and logical pluralism. Mind, 118, 295–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1973). In defense of convention T. In H. LeBlanc (Ed.), Truth, syntax, and modality (pp. 76–86). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (1990). The semantic foundations of logic: Predicate logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, J. (1990). The concept of logical consequence. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, J. (2008). Reflections on consequence. In Patterson (Ed.), New essays on Tarski and philosophy (pp. 263–299). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2009). Pluralism in logic. Review of Symbolic Logic, 2, 342–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freitag, W., & Zinke, A. (2012). The theory of form logic. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 21, 363–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goddu, G. (2001). What exactly is logical pluralism? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 80, 218–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (1996). Tarski on logical consequence. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 37, 125–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (1999). Logical truth and Tarskian logical truth. Synthese, 117, 375–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (2009). Rereading Tarski on logical consequence. Review of Symbolic Logic, 2, 249–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V. (2010). The logic manual. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (1996). Absolute necessities. Philosophical Perspectives, 10, 93–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, W. H. (1997). The concept of logical consequence. The Philosophical Review, 106, 365–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, W. E. (1921). Logic: Part I. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1970a). English as a formal language. In B. Visentini et al. (Eds.), Linguaggi nella societa et nella technica, Milan: Edizioni di Communita (pp. 188–221). Reprinted in R. H. Thomason (Ed.) (1974), Formal philosophy. Selected papers of richard montague (pp. 188–221). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Montague, R. (1970b). Universal grammar. Theoria, 36, 373–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, D. (2008). New essays on Tarski and philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peregrin, J., & Svoboda, V. (2013). Criteria for logical formalization. Synthese, 190, 2897–2924.

  • Priest, G. (1995). Etchemendy and logical consequence. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 25, 283–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray, G. (1996). Logical consequence. A defense of Tarski. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25, 617–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, S. (1994). Formal and material consequence. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23, 247–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Read, S. (2006). Monism: The one true logic. A Logical Approach to Philosophy. The Western Ontario Series in philosophy of science, 69, 193–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sagi, Gil. (2013). Models and logical consequence. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32(2), 191–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, M. (2001). Logical forms. An introduction to philosophical logic (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1996). Did Tarski commit ‘Tarski’s fallcy’? Journal of Symbolic Logic, 61, 653–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1956). Logic, semantics, metamathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vecsey, Z. (2010). On the pluralistic conception of logic. Pragmatics and Cognition, 18, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indepted to Michael Baumgartner, Wolfgang Freitag, Wolfgang Spohn and Holger Sturm for discussions and comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexandra Zinke.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zinke, A. On exhibiting representational validity. Synthese 192, 1157–1171 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0607-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0607-y

Keywords

Navigation