Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 192, Issue 1, pp 25–41 | Cite as

Freedom and (theoretical) reason

  • Margaret Schmitt
Article

Abstract

In a recent series of papers, Matthias Steup has defended doxastic voluntarism against longstanding objections. Many of his arguments center on the following conditional: if we accept a compatibilist notion of voluntary control, then, in most instances, belief-formation is voluntary and doxastic voluntarism the correct view. Steup defends two versions of this conditional. The first is universal, moving from compatibilism considered generally to doxastic voluntarism: if compatibilism is true, then doxastic voluntarism is true. The second is more particular, moving from the specific form of reasons-responsive compatibilism to doxastic voluntarism: if reasons-responsive compatibilism is true, then doxastic voluntarism is true. I argue that Steup’s arguments for both conditionals fail, in which case we lack reason to believe in either of them. In the final section of the paper, I argue that the impossibility of epistemic akrasia provides prima facie reason to think the latter conditional is false.

Keywords

Doxastic voluntarism Free will Compatibilism  Epistemic reasons 

Notes

Acknowledgments

This paper has been helped by many. I want to especially thank the following people for providing very instructive comments: Jeff Speaks, Tim Perrine, Will Reckner, Zac Bachmann, and Philip Swenson. Thank you also to attendees of the 2014 UCLA/USC graduate student conference and the SCP session at the 2014 ACPA meeting.

References

  1. Adler, J. (2002). Akratic believing. Philosophical Studies, 110, 1–27.Google Scholar
  2. Alston, W. (1989). Epistemic justification: Essays in the theory of knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  4. Bennett, J. (1990). Why is belief involuntary? Analysis, 50, 87–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Fischer, J. M. (2012). Responsibility and autonomy: The problem of mission creep. Philosophical Issues, 22, 165–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Hieronymi, P. (2006). Controlling attitudes. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 87, 45–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Hieronymi, P. (2008). Responsibility for believing. Synthese, 161, 357–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Hurley, S. (1989). Natural reasons. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Levy, Neil. (2004). Epistemic akrasia and the subsumption of evidence. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 4, 149–156.Google Scholar
  11. Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Owens, D. (2002). Epistemic akrasia. The Monist, 85, 381–397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Smith, A. M. (2005). Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics, 115, 236–271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Steup, M. (2008). Doxastic freedom. Synthese, 161, 375–392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Steup, M. (2011). Belief, voluntariness, and intentionality. Dialectica, 4, 537–559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Steup, M. (2012). Belief, control and intentionality. Synthese, 188, 145–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action: Elementary structures of practice and practical thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Vogler, C. (2002). Reasonably vicious. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of Notre DameNotre DameUSA

Personalised recommendations