Abstract
A natural language argument may be valid in at least two nonequivalent senses: it may be interpretationally or representationally valid (Etchemendy in The concept of logical consequence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1990). Interpretational and representational validity can both be formally exhibited by classical first-order logic. However, as these two notions of informal validity differ extensionally and first-order logic fixes one determinate extension for the notion of formal validity (or consequence), some arguments must be formalized by unrelated nonequivalent formalizations in order to formally account for their interpretational or representational validity, respectively. As a consequence, arguments must be formalized subject to different criteria of adequate formalization depending on which variant of informal validity is to be revealed. This paper develops different criteria that formalizations of an argument have to satisfy in order to exhibit the latter’s interpretational or representational validity.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.


Notes
The problem of systematizing logical formalization has also been addressed from a different angle in the literature. Instead of developing criteria of adequate formalization, authors as Davidson (1984), Chomsky (1977), Massey (1975), or Montague (1974), implicitly or explicitly subscribe to the ambitious project to define effective formalization procedures. This second thread in the formalization literature will be sidestepped in this paper.
Two FOL formulas \(\phi \) and \(\psi \) are said to be unrelated iff neither \(\phi \) is a specification of \(\psi \) nor vice versa and there does not exist a formula \(\chi \) that is a specification of both \(\phi \) and \(\psi \). For the relevant notion of specification cf. (Brun (2004), p. 320) or (Lampert and Baumgartner (2010), pp. 89–90).
Similarly, (Shapiro (1998), p. 137).
Essentially, this is what (Shapiro (2005), p. 663) dubs the blended view of models. I prefer to stick to Etchemendy’s original label “interpretational view”, because it emphasizes the core difference from the representational view.
Correspondence schemes have a very different function in the representational framework. In that framework they fix the interpretation of formal languages. Cf. Sect. 4 below.
In this respect the version of \(r\)-correctness presented here differs considerably from the versions developed by Blau (1977) and Brun (2004), who both only require correspondence of truth conditions relative to the subset of models \(\mathfrak{M }^{\scriptscriptstyle \phi }_k\) that provide what Blau and Brun call suitable interpretations of \(\phi \). For a detailed criticism of this latter approach cf. Baumgartner and Lampert (2008).
According to the convention adopted in Sect. 3, I say that arguments and their formalizations are true if they are truth-preserving in corresponding possible worlds and models, respectively, and false otherwise.
In Baumgartner and Lampert (2008), we argue that, from the representational perspective, there is no clear distinction between logical formalization and semantic analysis.
In this regard, \(r\)-correctness differs significantly from \(i\)-correctness. While formalizations of a statement \(\varPhi \) that introduce arbitrary tautologous elements not contained in \(\varPhi \) cannot be seen to model\(^*\) permissible reinterpretations of \(\varPhi \), formalizations of \(\varPhi \) model\(^*\) the truth conditions of \(\varPhi \) even if they feature an excessive tautologous surplus, provided that (IN) is respected.
References
Barwise, J., & Etchemendy, J. (1999). Language, proof and logic. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Baumgartner, M., & Lampert, T. (2008). Adequate formalization. Synthese, 164, 93–115.
Beall, J. C., & Restall, G. (2006). Logical pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Blau, U. (1977). Die dreiwertige Logik der Sprache. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Brun, G. (2004). Die richtige Formel. Philosophische Probleme der logischen Formalisierung. Ontos: Frankfurt a.M.
Brun, G. (2008). Formalization and the objects of logic. Erkenntnis, 69, 1–30.
Brun, G. (2012). Adequate formalization and De Morgan’s argument. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 85, 325–335.
Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. A. (2009). Modalism and logical pluralism. Mind, 118(470), 295–321.
Chiswell, I., & Hodges, W. (2007). Mathematical logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chomsky, N. (1977). Essays on form and interpretation. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Davidson, D. (1967). The logical form of action sentences. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action (pp. 81–95). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Epstein, R. L. (1990). The semantic foundations of logic: Propositional logics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Epstein, R. L. (1994). The semantic foundations of logic: Predicate logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Etchemendy, J. (1990). The concept of logical consequence. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Field, H. (2009). Pluralism in logic. Review of Symbolic Logic, 2(2), 342–359.
Gómez-Torrente, M. (1996). Tarski on logical consequence. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 37, 125–151.
Hale, B. (1996). Absolute necessities. Philosophical Perspectives, 10, 93–117.
Hodes, H. T. (1984). Logicism and the ontological commitments of arithmetic. Journal of Philosophy, 81(3), 123–149.
Hodges, W. (2001). Elementary predicate logic. In D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (2 ed.), Volume 1, (pp. 1–130). Dordrecht: Kluwer. Academic Publishers.
Jackson, B. (2007). Beyond logical form. Philosophical Studies, 132, 347–380.
Lampert, T., & Baumgartner, M. (2010). The problem of validity proofs. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 80, 79–109.
Massey, G. J. (1975). Are there any good arguments that bad arguments are bad? Philosophy in Context, 4, 61–77.
McFetridge, I. (1990). Logical necessity: Some issues. In J. Haldane & R. Scruton (Eds.), Logical necessity and other essays by Ian G. McFetridge (pp. 135–154). London: Aristotelian Society.
Montague, R. (1974). Formal philosophy: Selected papers of Richard Montague. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Ray, G. (1996). Logical consequence: A defense of Tarski. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25(6), 617–677.
Read, S. (1994). Formal and material consequence. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23, 247–265.
Russell, G. (2008). One true logic? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 37(6), 593–611.
Sainsbury, M. (2001). Logical forms. An introduction to philosophical logic (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Shalkowski, S. A. (2004). Logic and absolute necessity. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 55–82.
Shapiro, S. (1998). Logical consequence: Models and modality. In M. Schirn (Ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematics Today (pp. 131–156). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shapiro, S. (2005). Logical consequence, proof theory, and model theory. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic (pp. 651–671). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sher, G. (1996). Did Tarski commit ‘Tarski’s fallacy’? Journal of Symbolic Logic, 61, 653–686.
Tarski, A. (1956). Logic, semantics, metamathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Vecsey, Z. (2010). On the pluralistic conception of logic. Pragmatics & Cognition, 18, 1–16.
Wittgenstein, L. (1995). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a. M.
Acknowledgments
I am particularly indebted to Timm Lampert for countless discussions about the topics of this paper and for our common work on logical formalization. Moreover, I thank Wolfgang Spohn, Jochen Briesen, Alexandra Zinke, Brian Leahy and the anonymous referees of this journal for helpful comments on earlier drafts. Finally, the paper has profited from discussions with audiences at two research colloquia at the Humboldt University Berlin and the University of Konstanz.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Baumgartner, M. Exhibiting interpretational and representational validity. Synthese 191, 1349–1373 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0331-z
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0331-z