Skip to main content
Log in

Towards closure on closure

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Tracking theories of knowledge are widely known to have the consequence that knowledge is not closed. Recent arguments by Vogel and Hawthorne claim both that there are no legitimate examples of knowledge without closure and that the costs of theories that deny closure are too great. This paper considers the tracking theories of Dretske and Nozick and the arguments by Vogel and Hawthorne. We reject the arguments of Vogel and Hawthorne and evaluate the costs of closure denial for tracking theories of knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Adams F. (1986) The function of epistemic justification. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16: 465–492

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams F. (2003) Epistemology. In: McHenry L., Yagisawa T. (eds) Reflections on philosophy (2nd ed., pp 81–101). Longman Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams F. (2004) Knowledge. In: Floridi L. (Ed.) The blackwell guide to the philosophy of information and computing. Basil Blackwell, Oxford, pp 228–236

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams F. (2005) Tracking theories of knowledge. Veritas 50: 1–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams F., Clarke M. (2005) Resurrecting the tracking theories. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83: 207–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi R. (1995) Deductive closure, defeasibility, and skepticism: A reply to feldman. Philosophical Quarterly 45: 494–499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker J.A., Adams F. (2010) Epistemic closure and skepticism. Logos & Episteme 1(2): 221–246

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, J. A., & Adams, F. (forthcoming). Conclusive reasons, knowledge, and action. Philosophical Issues, 22.

  • BonJour L. (1987) Nozick, externalism, and skepticism. In: Luper-Foy S. (Ed.) The possibility of knowledge. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, MD, pp 297–313

    Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner A. (1985) Scepticism and epistemic closure. Philosophical Topics 13: 89–117

    Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner A. (2004) Strategies for refuting closure for knowledge. Analysis 64: 333–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K. (1995) Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review 104: 1–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (1970) Epistemic operators. Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–1023

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (1971) Conclusive reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (1972) Contrastive statements. Philosophical Review 81: 411–437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT/Bradford, Cambridge,MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (2005a) The case against closure. In: Steup M., Sosa E. (eds) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford, pp 13–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (2005b) Reply to Hawthorne. In: Steup M., Sosa E. (eds) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford, pp 43–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (2006) Information and closure. Erkenntnis 64: 409–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman R. (2001) Skeptical problems, contextualist solutions. Philosophical Studies 103: 61–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton R. (1987) Nozick’s epistemology. In: Luper-Foy S. (Ed.) The possibility of knowledge. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, MD, pp 163–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne J. (2004) Knowledge and lotteries. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne J. (2005) The case for closure. In: Steup M., Sosa E. (eds) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford, pp 26–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller M. (1999) Relevant alternatives and closure. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77: 196–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein P. (2004) Closure matters: Skepticism and easy knowledge. Philosophical Issues 14: 165–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (forthcoming). Nozick on knowledge. In S. Kripke (Ed.), Collected Papers (Vol. 1.) Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Morton A., Karjalainen A. (2003) Contrastive knowledge. Philosophical Explorations 6: 74–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R. (1981) Philosophical explanations. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive knowledge. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 235–271). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Stine G. (1976) Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and deductive closure. Philosophical Studies 29: 249–261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel J. (1990) Are there counterexamples to the closure principles?. In: Roth M., Ross G. (eds) Doubting. Kluwer Publishers, Dordrect, pp 113–127

    Google Scholar 

  • Warfield T. (2004) When epistemic closure does and does not fail: A lesson from the history of epistemology. Analysis 64: 35–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fred Adams.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Adams, F., Barker, J.A. & Figurelli, J. Towards closure on closure. Synthese 188, 179–196 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9922-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9922-8

Keywords

Navigation