Skip to main content
Log in

Forms of emergent interaction in General Process Theory

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

General Process Theory (GPT) is a new (non-Whiteheadian) process ontology. According to GPT the domains of scientific inquiry and everyday practice consist of configurations of ‘goings-on’ or ‘dynamics’ that can be technically defined as concrete, dynamic, non-particular individuals called general processes. The paper offers a brief introduction to GPT in order to provide ontological foundations for research programs such as interactivism that centrally rely on the notions of ‘process,’ ‘interaction,’ and ‘emergence.’ I begin with an analysis of our common sense concept of activities, which plays a crucial heuristic role in the development of the notion of a general process. General processes are not individuated in terms of their location but in terms of ‘what they do,’ i.e., in terms of their dynamic relationships in the basic sense of one process being part of another. The formal framework of GPT is thus an extensional mereology, albeit a non-classical theory with a non-transitive part-relation. After a brief sketch of basic notions and strategies of the GPT-framework I show how the latter may be applied to distinguish between causal, mechanistic, functional, self-maintaining, and recursively self-maintaining interactions, all of which involve ‘emergent phenomena’ in various senses of the term.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Baas, N. (1992). Emergence, hierarchies, and hyperstructures. Paper presented at the Third Annual Artificial Life Conference, Santa Fe.

  • Bickhard M. (2003) Process and emergence: Normative function and representation. In: Seibt J. (eds) Processes: Analysis and applications of dynamic categories. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 121–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen W., Bickhard M. (2002) The process dynamics of normative function. The Monist 85: 3–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham B. (2001) The reemergence of ‘emergence’. Philosophy of Science 68: S62–S75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe P. (1992) Wesley Salmon’s process theory of causality and the conserved quantity theory. Philosophy of Science 59: 195–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche C., Køppe S., Stjernfelt F. et al (2000) Levels, emergence, and three versions of downward causation. In: Emmeche C. (eds) Downward causation. Aarhus University Press, Aarhus, pp 8–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker C.A. (2004) Asymptotics, reduction and emergence. British Journal for Philosophy of Science 55: 435–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys P. (1997) How properties emerge. Philosophy of Science 64: 1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J. (1993) Supervenience and mind: Selected philosophical essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P., Darden L., Craver C. (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67: 1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mourelatos A. (1978) Events, processes, and states. Linguistics and Philosophy 2: 415–434

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mourelatos A. (1986) Quality, structure and emergence in later pre-socratic philosophy. In: Cleary J. (eds) Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy. Lanham, NY, pp 127–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman D. (1996) Emergence and strange attractrors. Philosophy of Science 63: 245–261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Puntel L.B. (1993) The context principle, universals and primary states of affairs. American Philosophical Quarterly 30: 123–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Puntel L.B. (2006) Struktur und Sein. Tübingen, Mohr-Siebeck

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W.V.O. (1985) Events and reification. In: LePore E., McLaughlin B. (eds) Actions and events. Blackwell, Perspectives on the philosophy of D. Davidson. Oxford, pp 162–172

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher N. (1996) Process metaphysics. An introduction. SUNY-Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Rueger A. (2000) Robust supervenience and emergence. Philosophy of Science 67: 466–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon W. (1997) Causality and explanation: A reply to two critiques. Philosophy of Science 64: 461–477

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saywer K. (2004) The mechanisms of emergence. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34: 260–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder T. (2004) Functions from regulation. The Monist 87: 115–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J. (1990). Towards process ontology: A critical study in substance-ontological premises. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh, UMI-Publications.

  • Seibt J. (1995) Individuen als Prozesse: Zur prozeß-ontologischen Revision des Substanzparadigmas. Logos 2: 303–343

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. (1996) The myth of substance and the fallacy of misplaced concreteness. Acta Analytica 15: 61–76

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. (1996) Non-countable individuals: Why ‘one’ and the ‘same’ is not one and the same. Southwest Philosophy Review 12: 225–237

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. (1997) Existence in time: From substance to process. In: Faye J., Scheffler U., Urs M. (eds) Perspectives on time. Kluwer, Boston studies in philosophy of science. Dordrecht, pp 143–182

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J. (2000a). The dynamic constitution of things. In J. Faye et al. (Eds.), Facts and events. Poznan studies in philosophy of science (pp. 241–279).

  • Seibt J. (2000) Ontology as theory of categorial inference. In: Greimann D., Peres C. (eds) Wahrheit-Sein-Struktur. Auseinandersetzungen mit Metaphysik. Olms Verlag, Hildesheim, pp 272–297

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. (2001) Formal process ontology. In: Welty C., Smith B. (eds) Formal ontology in information systems: Collected papers from the second international conference. ACM Press, Ogunquit, pp 333–345

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. et al (2002) Quanta, tropes, or processes: On ontologies for QFT beyond the mythof substance. In: Kuhlmann M. (eds) Ontological aspects of quantum field theory. World Scientific, Singapore, pp 53–93–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J. (eds) (2003) Process theories: Analysis and applications of dynamic categories. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. (2004) Free process theory: Towards a typology of occurrences. Axiomathes 14: 23–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. (2004) General processes—a study in ontological category construction. Habilitationsschrift University of Konstanz, Germany

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J. (2005) Der Mythos der Substanz. In: Trettin K. (eds) Substanz—Neue Überlegungen zu einer klassischen Kategorie des Seienden. Klostermann, Frankfurt, pp 197–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J. (2007). Beyond endurance and perdurance: Recurrent dynamics. In: Kanzian C. (eds.) Persistence. Frankfurt, Ontos-Verlag, pp 133–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J. (2008). Mereology on processes (submitted).

  • Sellars W. (1981) Foundations for a metaphysics of pure processes. The Monist 64: 3–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons P. (1987) Parts, a study in ontology. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith T., Stevens G. (1996) Emergence, self-organization, and social interaction: Arousal dependent structure in social systems. Sociological Theory 14: 131–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soto A., Sonnenschein C. (2006) Emergentism by default: A view from the bench. Synthese 151: 361–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stout R. (1997) Processes. Philosophy 72: 119–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabery J. (2004) Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism. Philosophy of Science 71: 1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vendler Z. (1967) Linguistics and philosophy. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl H. (1978) Thematic relations and the semantic representation of verbs expressing change. Studies in Language 2: 199–233

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermaas P., Houkes W. (2003) Ascribing functions to technical artifacts: A challenge to the etiological account of functions. British Journal for Philosophy of Science 54: 261–289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead A.N. (1929) Process and reality. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W. (1986) Forms of aggregativity. In: Donegan A. (eds) Human nature and natural knowledge. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 259–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W. (1997) Aggregativity: Reductive heuristics for finding emergence. Philosophy of Science 64: S372–S384

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J. (2002) What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science 69: S366–S377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zemach E. (1970) Four ontologies. Journal of Philosophy 23: 231–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johanna Seibt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Seibt, J. Forms of emergent interaction in General Process Theory. Synthese 166, 479–512 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9373-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9373-z

Keywords

Navigation