Skip to main content
Log in

Can the skepticism debate be resolved?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

External world skeptics are typically opposed to admitting as evidence anything that goes beyond the purely phenomenal, and equally typically, they disown the use of rules of inference that might enable one to move from premises about the phenomenal alone to a conclusion about the external world. This seems to bar any a posteriori resolution of the skepticism debate. This paper argues that the situation is not quite so hopeless, and that an a posteriori resolution of the debate becomes possible once it is recognized that the skeptic holds overly defensive and ill-motivated positions vis-à-vis both evidence and inference, and that more reasonable ones are available. In stating these more reasonable positions, as well as in showing how they make possible an a posteriori resolution of the skepticism debate, the paper draws on the machinery of Bayesian epistemology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bergmann M. (2004). Epistemic circularity: Malignant and benign. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69: 709–727

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour L., Sosa E. (2003). Epistemic justification. Malden, MA, Blackwell Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne A. (2004). How hard are the sceptical paradoxes? Noûs 38: 299–325

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen D. (1983). Glymour on evidential relevance. Philosophy of Science 50: 471–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen D. (1994). Conservatism in epistemology. Noûs 28: 69–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen D. (2004). Putting logic in its place. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13: 57–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S. (2002). Basic knowledge and the problem of easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 309–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review 104: 1–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven I. (1999). Inference to the best explanation made coherent. Philosophy of Science (Proceedings) 66: S424–S435

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven I. (2002). Testing inference to the best explanation. Synthese 130: 355–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven I. (2005a). Evidence, explanation, and the empirical status of scientific realism. Erkenntnis 63: 253–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven I. (2005b). Wouldn’t it be lovely: Explanation and scientific realism. Metascience 14: 338–343

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2007). Underdetermination. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to the philosophy of science. London: Routledge (in press).

  • Douven I., Meijs W. (2006). Bootstrap confirmation made quantitative. Synthese 49: 97–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven I., Williamson T. (2006). Generalizing the lottery paradox. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 755–779

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J., Glymour C. (1988). What revisions does bootstrap testing need? Philosophy of Science 55: 260–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley R. (1992). The epistemology of belief and the epistemology of degrees of belief. American Philosophical Quarterly 29: 111–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaifman H. (1986). A theory of higher order probabilities. In: Halpern J. (eds) Theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge: Proceedings of the 1986 Conference. San Mateo CA, Morgan–Kaufmann, pp. 275–292

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour C. (1980). Theory and evidence. Princeton NJ, Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A. (1988). Empirical knowledge. Berkeley, University of California Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham P. (2007). The theoretical diagnosis of skepticism. Synthese 158: 19–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman G. (1973). Thought. Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich P. (1982). Probability and evidence. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson C. (1984). Bayesianism and support by novel facts. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35: 245–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson C. (2000). Hume’s problem: Induction and the justification of belief. Oxford, Clarendon Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey R. (1983). The logic of decision (2nd ed). Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce J. (2004). Bayesianism. In: Mele A.R., Rawling P. (eds) The Oxford handbook of rationality. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 132–155

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein P. (1985). The virtues of inconsistency. Monist 68: 105–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg H. (1961). Probability and the logic of rational belief. Middletown CT, Wesleyan University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed). London, Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher P. (1993). Betting on theories. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1962). Proof of an external world. Philosophical papers (pp. 126–149). New York: Collier Books.

  • Pryor J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34: 517–549

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryor J. (2004). What’s wrong with Moore’s argument?. Philosophical Issues 14: 349–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1926). Truth and probability. The foundations of mathematics, 1931 (pp. 156–198). London: Routledge.

  • Reichenbach H. (1938). Experience and prediction. Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E. (1997). Reflective knowledge in the best circles. Journal of Philosophy 94: 410–430

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vahid H. (2004). Varieties of epistemic conservatism. Synthese 141: 97–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford, Clarendon Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (1983). Theory comparison and relevant evidence. In: Earman J. (eds) Testing scientific theories. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, pp. 27–42

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford, Clarendon Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. Journal of Philosophy 87: 658–666

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel J. (2004). Skeptical arguments. Philosophical Issues 14: 426–455

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel J. (2005). The refutation of skepticism. In: Steup M., Sosa E. (eds) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Oxford, Blackwell Publishing, pp. 72–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright C. (1985). Facts and certainty. Proceedings of the British Academy 71: 429–472

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright C. (1991). Scepticism and dreaming: Imploding the demon. Mind 100: 87–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Igor Douven.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Douven, I. Can the skepticism debate be resolved?. Synthese 168, 23–52 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9311-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9311-0

Keywords

Navigation