Skip to main content
Log in

Perceptual systems and realism

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Constructivism undermines realism by arguing that experience is mediated by concepts, and that there is no direct way to examine those aspects of objects that belong to them independently of our conceptualizations; perception is theory-laden. To defend realism one has to show first that perception relates us directly with the world without any intermediary conceptual framework. The result of this direct link is the nonconceptual content of experience. Second, one has to show that part of the nonconceptual content extracted from the environment correctly represents features of mind independent objects. With regard to the first condition, I have argued elsewhere that a part of visual processing, which I call “perception,” is theory-neutral and nonconceptual. In this paper, facing the second demand, I argue that a part of the nonconceptual content of perception presents properties that are the properties of mind independent objects. I claim first that nonconceptual content is the appropriate level of analysis of the issue of realism since it avoids the main problems besetting various types of analysis of the issue at the level of beliefs about the world. Then I claim that a subset of the nonconceptual content presents features of objects in the environment as they really are.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bermudez J.L. (1995). Nonconceptual content: From perceptual experience to subpersonal computational states. Mind and Language 10(4): 333–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez J.L. (2003). Thinking without words. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard M.H. (2000). Dynamic representing and representational dynamics. In: Dietrich E., Markman A.B. (eds) Cognitive dynamics. Mahwall NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 31–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N. (1996). How can we find the neural correlate of consciousness. Trends in Neuroscience 19, 456–459

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonjour L. (2003). A version of internalist foundationalism. In: Bonjour L., Sosa E. (eds) Epistemic justification: Internalism vs. externalism, foundations vs. virtues. Oxford, Blackwell Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruce V., Green P.R. (1993). Visual perception: Physiology, psychology and ecology (2nd ed). Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D. (1983). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In: Dieter H. (eds) Kant oder Hegel. Stuttgart, Klett-Cotta

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene S., Kerszberg M., Changeux J.P. (1998). A neuronal model of global workspace in effortful cognitive tasks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA 95: 14529–14534

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D. (1978). Brainstorms. Montgomery, VT, Bradford Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (1993). Conscious experience. Mind 102(406): 263–283

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferster D. (1981). A comparison of binocular depth mechanisms in areas 17 and 18 of the cat visual cortex. The Journal of Physiology 311, 623–655

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J. (1994). The elm and the expert. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Glover S. (2004). Separate visual representations in the planning and control of action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27(1): 3–79

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale M.A., Milner D.A. (1992). Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends in Neuroscience 15, 20–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale M.A., Milner D.A. (2004). Sight unseen. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1998). Having thought. Harvard University Press.

  • Hollingworth A., Henderson J.M. (2002). Accurate visual memory for previously attended objects in natural scenes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 28(1): 113–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollingworth A., Williams C., Henderson J.M. (2001). To see and remember: Visually specific information is retained in memory from previously attended objects in natural scenes. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 8(4): 761–768

    Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff-Smith A. (1992). Beyond modularity: A developmental perspective on cognitive science. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P. (2001). Real realism: The Galilean strategy. Philosophical Review 110(2): 151–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamme V.A.F. (2000). Neural mechanisms of visual awareness: A linking proposition. Brain and Mind 1, 385–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamme V.A.F. (2003). Why visual attention and awareness are different. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(1): 12–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markie P.J. (2004). Nondoxastic perceptual evidence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXVIII(3): 530–554

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum M. (1964). Philosophy, science, and sense perception. Baltimore, MD, The Johns Hopkins University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into human representation and processing of visual information. San Francisco, CA, Freeman

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Harvard University Press.

  • Norman J. (2002). Two visual systems and two theories of perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, 73–144

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poggio G.F., Talbot W.H. (1981). Mechanisms of static and dynamic stereopsis in foveal cortex of the rhesus monkey. The Journal of Physiology 315, 469–492

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (1980). Models and reality. Journal of Symbolic Logic 45, 464–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn Z. (2003). Seeing and visualizing. Cambridge, MA, The MIT University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W.V.O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA, The MIT University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W.V.O. (1970). On the reasons for indeterminacy of translation. Journal of Philosophy LXVII, 178–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos A. (1997). Resource limitations in early infancy and its role in successful learning: A connectionist approach. Human Development 40(5): 293–319

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos A. (2001a). Is perception informationally encapsulated? The issue of the theory-ladenness of perception. Cognitive Science 25, 423–451

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos A. (2001b). Reentrant pathways and the theory-ladenness of observation. Philosophy of Science 68, 187–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos A. (2006). Defending realism on the proper ground. Philosophical Psychology 19(1): 1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (forthcoming). Perception and cognition: How do psychology and neural science inform philosophy. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press, a Bradford Series Book

  • Raftopoulos A., Müller V. (2006a). The nonconceptual content of experience. Mind and Language 27(2): 187–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos A., Müller V. (2006b). Deictic codes, object files, and demonstrative reference. Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 72(2): 251–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E. (2003). Beyond internal foundations to external virtues. In: Bonjour L., Sosa E. (eds) Epistemic justification: Internalism vs externalism, foundations vs. virtues. Oxford, Blackwell Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke E.S. (1990). Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science 14, 29–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich S.P. (1985). Could man be an irrational animal?. Synthese 64, 115–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye M. (2005). Nonconceptual content, richness and fineness of grain. In: Gendler T., Hawthorne J. (eds) Perceptual experience. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulmann A., Richards W. (eds) (1990). Image understanding. Norwood, NJ, Ablex

    Google Scholar 

  • Vision G. (1997). Problems of vision. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Vision G. (1998). Perceptual content. Philosophy 73, 395–428

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Athanasios Raftopoulos.

Additional information

This paper was mostly written when I was a fellow at the Center of Philosophy of Science in the University of Pittsburgh during the Spring Semester of 2005–2006. A draft of this paper was presented both at the Center’s colloquium and at one of the informal discussion meetings of the fellows. I have very much benefited from the discussion that followed the presentation of the paper and so I would like to thank Gabriele de Anna, Carla Fehr, Malcolm Forster, Lilly Gurova, Nikolay Milkov, and Wang Wei. I am especially indebted to the director of the Center Professor John Norton whose astute comments made me think hard about the issues discussed in the paper. Several of my arguments in Sect. 4 are the result of John’s concerns with the earlier draft of the paper. I would also like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for helping me clarify several points in the paper. Thanks to them (especially the second one) the paper is considerably better than it would have been without them.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Raftopoulos, A. Perceptual systems and realism. Synthese 164, 61–91 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-007-9216-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-007-9216-3

Keywords

Navigation