Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 151, Issue 3, pp 561–569 | Cite as

Emergence and reduction: Reply to Kim

  • Ausonio MarrasEmail author
Original Paper

Abstract

In this paper I examine Jaegwon Kim’s view that emergent properties are irreducible to the base properties on which they supervene. Kim’s view assumes a model of ‘functional reduction’ which he claims to be substantially different from the traditional Nagelian model. I dispute this claim and argue that the two models are only superficially different, and that on either model, properly understood, it is possible to draw a distinction between a property’s being reductively identifiable with its base property and a property’s being reductively explainable in terms of it. I propose that we should take as the distinguishing feature of emergent properties that they be truly novel properties, i.e., ontologically distinct from the ‘base’ properties which they supervene on. This only requires that emergent properties cannot be reductively identified with their base properties, not that they cannot be reductively explained in terms of them. On this conception the set of emergent properties may well include mental properties as conceived by nonreductive physicalists.

Keywords

Emergence Jaegwon Kim Nonreductive physicalism Reduction Reductive explanation Supervenience 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Beckermann A. (1992). Supervenience, emergence, and reduction. In: Beckermann A. (eds). Emergence or Reduction?. De Gruyter, Berlin and New YorkGoogle Scholar
  2. Bickle J. (1998). Psychoneural reduction. MIT Press, Cambrdige, MAGoogle Scholar
  3. Chalmers D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford University Press, New York and OxfordGoogle Scholar
  4. Churchland P. (1985). Reduction, qualia, and the direct introspection of brain states. Journal of Philosophy 82, 8–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Hooker C. (1981). Towards a general theory of reduction. Dialogue, 20, 38–60, 201–236, 496–529Google Scholar
  6. Kim, J. (1984). Concepts of supervenience. In Supervenience and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
  7. Kim, J. (1990). Supervenience as a philosophical concept. In Supervenience and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
  8. Kim J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  9. Kim J. (2003). Blocking causal drainage and other maintenance chores with mental causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67, 151–176CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Loar B. (1990). Phenomenal states. Philosophical Perspectives 4, 81–108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Marras A. (1998). Kim’s principle of explanatory exclusion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76, 439–451CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Marras A. (2000). Critical notice of Kim (1998). Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30, 137–160Google Scholar
  13. Marras A. (2002). Kim on reduction. Erkenntnis 57, 231–257CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Nagel E. (1961). The structure of science. Harcourt, Brace, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  15. Richardson R. (1979). Functionalism and reductionism. Philosophy of Science 46, 533–558CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Ross D., Spurrett D. (2004). What to say to a skeptical metaphysician: a defense manual for cognitive and behavioral scientists. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27, 603–627CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Schaffner K. (1967). Approaches to reduction. Philosophy of Science 34, 137–147CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyTalbot College, University of Western OntarioOntarioCanada

Personalised recommendations