Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

In this article I engage with Tarunabh Khaitan’s scholarship on expressive norms. Khaitan argues that the expressive value of a legal speech-act is independent of its consequences. I query the analytical moves that inform this argument. Specifically, I show that (1) Khaitan’s account of the illocutionary force of a speech-act is a particular displacement of linguistic theory into constitutional philosophy; (2) using Kazuo Ishiguro’s The Remains of the Day as a talking point, the focus on the illocutionary force of a legal expression can confound constitutive reasons that lend weight to such an expression; and (3) the claim that expressive norms are consequence-independent is diluted once it becomes evident that such a claim is premised on epistemic problems rather than moral arguments. Finally, I argue that to work towards a society characterised by non-humiliation, it pays to focus on the constitutive reasons and consequences of expressive norms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Symposium on The Expressive Dimension of Governmental Action: Philosophical and Legal Perspectives (2001) 60 Maryland Law Review 492.

  2. Professor Khaitan is currently Professor of Public Law and Legal Theory at Oxford University.

  3. Anderson and Pildes [3, p. 1527], cited in Khaitan [29, 4 fn 24].

  4. The value on which all legal actions are premised per Hellman is that ‘we must matter equally to our government.’ Thus, her account is tethered to the value of non-discrimination, while the Anderson-Pildes framework is broader. The challenge is for a judge to ascertain whether a particular law or policy expresses this value; ‘hence meanings attributed to state actions will not be fully objective or social’ [20, p. 69].

  5. Hence Smith:

    ‘Anderson and Pildes make no effort to show that a legislature or "the democratic State" could in fact satisfy the conditions that they have so carefully specified-the conditions, that is, of their "members [being] jointly committed to expressing [a particular meaning] as a body" -or that these groups could engage in the "successful conversational exchange" attributed to partners in hiking, cooking, and shoveling snow. Instead, they promptly retreat to a different (and all too familiar) position: that we often treat laws as if they reflected some such collective intention. Their rigorous "if and only if' quickly lapses into the licentious "as if."’ [61: 551].

  6. ‘I also argue that the expressive function of law makes most sense in connection with efforts to change norms and if legal statements produce bad consequences, they should not be enacted even if they seem reasonable or noble’ [66, p. 2025].

  7. Khaitan cites Anderson-Pildes and Sunstein sequentially when he develops his propositions [29, p. 4].

  8. Ibid.

  9. There is some doubt as to whether Austin preferred convention or intention as the central determinant of force of a speech-act. He does say that ‘force is determined by an accepted conventional procedure having a certain conventional effect’ Austin [7, p. 14]. But it is not clear whether he was referring to illocutionary force.

  10. ‘Searle's view is flawed because the completion of the communicative act requires that the addressee understand what the speaker has said’ [3, p. 1572]. Searle does have an account of ‘collective intentionality’ that Anderson–Pildes does not engage with. Searle’s philosophical view in any event sharply diverges with Anderson–Pildes as it is not the product of cooperative behaviour but something that seems to be a ‘primitive phenomenon’ [58, pp. 24–26].

  11. As Cooren has shown, this is a Habermasian ‘displacement’ in his reinterpretation of speech-act theory [11].

  12. Searle says that constitutive rules define ‘new forms of behaviour,’ but this would be a confusing usage of ‘behaviour’ when we bring in mediators such as legal institutions into the mix. If speech-acts are performed by legal institutions, then it is their behaviour that we would be concerned about in Searle’s framework, rather than a reference to the behaviour of the citizenry.

  13. In relation to whether such rules can be identified, Searle remarks that ‘the effort to state the rules for the performance of speech-acts can also be regarded as a test of the hypothesis that there are constitutive rules underlying speech acts. If we are unable to give any satisfactory rule formulations, our failure could be construed as partially disconfirming evidence against the hypothesis.’.

  14. In this regard, I assume that a statement by a legal institution is intentional. I do not ascribe a strong intentionality; a legal institution may well be giving effect to reasons such as social norms. But at the very least, a legal institution plays a mediating role as a speaker. This is in conformity with Austin and Searle without necessarily subscribing to the intentionalist account by Bach and Harnish.

  15. The classic exposition of the ‘constrained view’ or the limited potential for the Supreme Court to effect social change using Brown as an example is Rosenberg [53, pp. 42–93].

  16. As Reed [51] puts it:

    “Segregated education, not segregated movie houses or drinking fountains, was the foundation of Jim Crow. Segregated education was the line of demarcation between oppressor and oppressed; it policed the boundary of the racial hierarchy. Which side of that line you stood on determined where you could go in the world. Even if you were fortunate enough to be educated in one of the few excellent segregated schools, you faced severely limited horizons. The classic example is W.E.B. Du Bois. The first black American to get a Ph.D. from Harvard, he could not find an academic appointment at a white institution in the United States. That was the point at which the confinement of the horizon was most cruel.”

  17. The ‘miniscule size of the population’ seeking protections was found to be an argument against such members of the LGBTQ community.

  18. Recall Khaitan’s third proposition in his account of expressive norms [29, p. 4].

  19. As Sturgeon points out, it is important to not to confuse consequentialists with economists [65, p. 514].

  20. In the absence of explicit safeguards, there could well be a convergence of information that could be used by regulatory bodies for undisclosed and unanticipated purposes—especially ones like the Intelligence Bureau that is beyond the reach of right to information legislation—a phenomenon that has been referred to as ‘functional creep’ [62, p. 214].

  21. The dissenting opinion in Puttaswamy II has been relied on by the Supreme Court of Jamaica in a robust way to find its biometric identification law unconstitutional on privacy grounds [83].

  22. Mukherjee makes this point with respect to the legality of ordinances made by state governments [45]; Khaitan makes this point with respect to fundamental rights in general [35]; Kamil makes this point specifically with respect to the right to privacy [27].

  23. See Sect. 4.1 above.

References

  1. Adler, Matthew. 2000. Expressive theories of law: A sceptical overview. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148 (5): 1363–1501.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ahmad, Faizi Noor. Aadhaar judgment and hunger deaths: An unsettled debate. The Week, October 03, 2018.

  3. Elizabeth, Anderson, and Pildes Richard. 2000. Expressive theories of law: A general restatement. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148 (5): 1504–1575.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Anderson, Elizabeth. 1993. Values in ethics and economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Austin, John Langshaw. 1961. Philosophical papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Austin, John Langshaw. 1962. How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Bach, Kent, and Robert Harnish. 1979. Linguistic communication and speech acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Bhuwania, Anuj. 2017. Courting the people: Public interest litigation in post-emergency India. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Chandrachud, Abhinav. 2013. Wednesbury reformulated: Proportionality and the supreme court of India. Oxford University Commonwealth Law Journal 13: 191–208.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Church, Jennifer. 2010. Seeing reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (3): 638–670.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cooren, Francois. 2000. Toward another ideal speech situation: A critique of Habermas’ reinterpretation of speech act theory’. Quarterly Journal of Speech 80 (3): 295–317.

    Google Scholar 

  12. De, Rohit. 2018. A people’s constitution: The everyday life of law in the Indian republic. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Fonioková, Zuzana. 2006. The Butler’s suspicious dignity: Unreliable narration in Kazuo Ishiguro’s The Remains of the Day. Brno Studies in English 32 (1): 87–98.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gardner, John. 2012. Law as a leap of faith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Geisinger, Alex, and Michael Ashley Stein. 2007. A theory of expressive international law. Vanderbilt law Review 60 (1): 77–130.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Godsil, Rachel. 2003. Expressivism, empathy and equality. University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform 36 (2): 247–304.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Habermas, Jurgen. 1984. The theory of communicative action: Reason and the rationalisation of society. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Hage, Jaap, and Aleksander Peczenik. 2000. Law, morals and defeasibility. Ratio Juris 13 (3): 305–325.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Harvard Law Review. Rights in Flux: Nonconsequentialism, Consequentialism and the Judicial Role 130: 1436–1457.

  20. Hellman, Deborah. 2003. The expressive dimension of equal protection. Minnesota Law Review. 85 (1): 1–70.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Hellman, Deborah. 2008. When is discrimination wrong?. Harvard, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Hesni, Samia. 2018. Illocutionary Frustration. Mind 127: 947–976.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Hornsby, Jennifer, and Rae Langton. 1998. Free speech and illocution. Legal Theory 4: 21–37.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ishiguro, Kazuo. 1989. The remains of the day. London: Faber & Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Jacobsen, Elida. 2013. Unique identification: Inclusion and surveillance in the Indian biometric assemblage. Security Dialogue 43: 457–474.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Kahan, Dan. 1996. ‘What do alternative sanctions mean’? University of Chicago Law Review 63: 591–653.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kamil, Mariam. 2017. Puttaswamy: Jury still out on some privacy concerns? Indian Law Review 1 (2): 190–204.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kannabiran, Kalpana. 2012. Tools of justice: Non-discrimination and the Indian constitution. New Delhi: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Khaitan, Tarunabh. 2012. Dignity as an expressive norm. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 32 (1): 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Khaitan, Tarunabh. 2015. A theory of discrimination law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Khaitan, Tarunabh. 2018. Directive principles and the expressive accommodation of ideological dissenters. International Journal of Constitutional Law 16 (2): 389–420.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Khaitan, Tarunabh. 2019. Constitutional directives: Morally-committed political constitutionalism. Modern Law Review 82 (4): 603–632.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Khaitan, Tarunabh. 2018a. Inclusive Pluralism or Majoritarian Nationalism: Article 15, Section 377 and Who We Really Are. Indian Constitutional Law and Philosophy, July 9, 2018. https://indconlawphil.wordpress.com/2018/07/09/inclusive-pluralism-or-majoritarian-nationalism-article-15-section-377-and-who-we-really-are/.

  34. Khaitan, Tarunabh. 2018b. Three Reflections on the S 377 Case. Law and Other Things, July 18, 2018. https://lawandotherthings.com/2018/07/three-reflections-on-the-s-377-case/.

  35. Khaitan, Tarunabh. 2008. Beyond reasonableness—A rigorous standard of review for Article 15 infringement. Journal of the Indian Law Institute 50 (2): 177–208.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Krygier, M. 2007. Law and the State. University of New South Wales Research Paper 22. https://law.bepress.com/unswwps-flrps/art22.

  37. Kumar, Ashwani. 2017. The resilience of our liberalism: On the right to privacy. The Hindu. May 12, 2017.

  38. Lessig, Lawrence. 1995. The regulation of social meaning. University of Chicago Law Review 62 (3): 944–1045.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Levine, Madison Julia. 2019. Biometric identification in India versus the right to privacy: Core constitutional features, defining citizens’ interests and the implications of biometric identification in the United States. University of Miami Law Review 73 (2): 618–654.

    Google Scholar 

  40. MacCormick, Neil, and Joseph Raz. 1972. Voluntary obligations and normative powers. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society supp. 46: 59–102.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Margalit, Avishai. 1996. The decent society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Marsons, Lee. 2018. Bifurcation, unification and calibration: A comparison of Indian and English approaches to proportionality. Indian Law Review 2 (1): 26–50.

    Google Scholar 

  43. McAdams, Richard. 2015. The expressive powers of law: Theories and limits. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Miller, David. 1997. Equality and justice. Ratio 10: 222–237.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Mukherjee, Gaurav. 2018. The supreme court and executive law-making: the afterlife of failed ordinances in Krishna Kumar Singh II. Indian Law Review 1 (3): 312–326.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Munrow, Andrew. 2013. Reading austin rhetorically. Philosophy & Rhetoric 46 (1): 22–43.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Oishi, Etsuko. 2006. Austin’s Speech Act Theory and the Speech Situation Esercizi Filosofici 1: 1 -14.

  48. Pildes, Richard. 1998. Why rights are not trumps: Social meanings, expressive harms and constitutionalism. Journal of Legal Studies 27: 725–763.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Rao, R., and G. Greenleaf. 2013. Subverting ID from above and below: The uncertain shaping of India’s new instrument of e-governance. Surveillance & Society 11 (3): 287–300.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ramanathan, Usha. 2010. A unique identity bill. Economic and Political Weekly 45 (30): 10–14.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Reed, Douglas. Measuring the impact of Brown v. Board. Paper presented at Woodrow Wilson International Center for scholars conference, Washington, DC.

  52. Rosen, Michael. 2012. Dignity: Its history and meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Rosenberg, Gerald N. 2008. The hollow hope: Can courts bring about social change?. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Roy, Suryapratim. Are the scales of justice lopsided? The Hindustan Times, April 24, 2013.

  55. Roy, Suryapratim. 2014. Privileging (some forms of) interdisciplinarity and interpretation: Methods in comparative law. International Journal of Constitutional Law 12 (3): 786–807.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Searle, John. 1969. Speech-acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Searle, John. 1979. Meaning and expression: Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Searle, John. 1995. The construction of social reality. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Sen, Kaushik. 2015. Aadhar: Wrong number or big brother calling? Socio-legal Review 11: 85–108.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Sloane, Richard. 2007. The expressive capacity of international punishment: The limits of the national law analogy and the potential of international criminal law. Stanford Journal of International Law 43: 39–94.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Smith, Steven. 2001. Expressivist jurisprudence and the depletion of meaning. Maryland Law Review 60 (3): 507–577.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Sriraman, Tarangini. 2018. In pursuit of proof: A history of identification documents in India. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Srivas, Anuj and Venkatanarayanan Anand. 2018. How did the election commission link 300 million voter IDs to aadhaar in just a few months? The Wire, November 9, 2018.

  64. Stiles, W. 1981. Classification of intersubjective illocutionary acts. Language in Society 10 (2): 227–249.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Sturgeon, Nicholas. 1996. Anderson on reason and value. Ethics 106 (3): 509–524.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Sunstein, Cass. 1996. On the expressive function of law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 144: 2021–2055.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Sunstein, Cass. 1996. Social norms and social roles. Columbia Law Review 96: 903–968.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Sunstein, Cass. Did brown matter? New Yorker May 3, 2004.

  69. Tushnet, Mark. 2004. Some legacies of Brown v. Board of Education. Virginia Law Review 90: 1693–1720.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Wall, Kathleen. 1994. The remains of the day and its challenge to theories of unreliable narration. The Journal of Narrative Technique 24 (1): 18–42.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Winn, Peter. 1991. Legal ritual. Law and Critique 2: 207–232.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Wood, Allen W. 1999. Kant’s ethical thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Wringe, Bill. 2016. An expressive theory of punishment. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

Cases Cited

  1. Brown v Board of Education 347 US 483 (1954).

  2. Egan v Canada [1995] e SCR 513 (Can) [170].

  3. Re Marriage Cases 183 P 3d (Cal 2008).

  4. Loving v Virginia 388 US 1 (1967).

  5. Wilkinson v Kitzinger [2006] EWHC 2022 (Fam).

  6. Navtej Singh Johar v. Union of India WP (Cri.) No. 76/2016.

  7. Suresh Kumar Koushal v. Naz Foundation (2014) 1 SCC 1.

  8. KS Puttaswamy v Union of India AIR 2017 SC 416.

  9. K. S. Puttaswamy v Union of India, Writ Petition (Civil) No. 494 of 2012 (Sup. Ct. India Sep 26, 2018).

  10. Julian Robinson v Attorney General of Jamaica, CLAIM NO 2018HCV01788 (2019 JMFC Full 04).

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this article were prepared for the Irish Jurisprudence Society and Global Constitutionalism Seminar. I am grateful to Tim Murphy, David Prendergast, Oran Doyle, Garrett Barden and Dimitry Kochenov for comments on earlier drafts. I also thank the reviewers of this article for reading my work with interest.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Suryapratim Roy.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roy, S. Constitutive Reasons and Consequences of Expressive Norms. Int J Semiot Law 34, 389–408 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-020-09705-w

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-020-09705-w

Keywords

Navigation