Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Law’s Cultural Project and the Claim to Universality or the Equivocalities of a Familiar Debate

  • Published:
International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue internationale de Sémiotique juridique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Do our present circumstances allow us to defend a specific connection (that specific connection) between «legal rules», «moral claims» and «democratic principles» which we may say is granted by an unproblematic presupposition of universality or by an «acultural» experience of modernity? In order to discuss this question, this paper invokes the challenge-visée of a plausible reinvention of Law’s autonomous project (a reinvention which may be capable of critically re-thinking and re-experiencing Law’s constitutive cultural-civilizational originarium in a «limit-situation» such as our own). The discussion is developed by recognising that the claim to universality is not only incompatible with a substantive conception of juridicalness as validity but also sustained with difficulty by a procedural representation of discourse and rationality (a representation which, against its own conclusion-claims, could also be said to be culturally and civilizationally bounded). Not forgetting some specific features of contemporary juridical pluralism—namely that which emerges from the counterpoint between semiotic groups or interpretative communities (and their differently assumed claims of intersemioticity concerning the signifier law)—this train of reflection diagnoses briefly a sequence of complementary main difficulties (as «obstacles» to recognising Law’s demand as an unmistakable cultural project), namely those arising from the formalistic normativistic inheritance (confounding legal autonomy with isolationism), from the challenges and seductions of practical holism (justifying a continuum in which Law’s project loses its sense and autonomy), and also from the familiar debate between exclusive and inclusive versions of positivism and non-positivism (a debate which establishes-consecrates an equivocal counterpoint between Law and Morality).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. So that we may distinguish two versions of positivism (exclusive and inclusive) and three versions of non-positivism (exclusive, super-inclusive, inclusive) [3, pp. 267–270].

  2. As we know, the importance of distinguishing between the analytical and the normative group of arguments (both including empirical arguments) to reconstruct the controversy of legal positivism is mainly developed in [2], passim. We shall use mainly the latest version of this text, which appeared as [4] (not only a translation by Bonnie and Stanley Paulson, but also a new version, with several detailed alterations proposed by Alexy himself), pp. 20 ff. («Critique of Positivistic Concepts of Law»).

  3. If not explicitly to the «idea of correct morality as justified morality» [4, pp. 80–81].

  4. «As the claim to objectivity (…) and truth (…), the claim to correctness is addressed to all» and «this is true without qualification as far as universal morality is concerned» [3 , p. 261 and note 17].

  5. An answer capable of entering into a certain «debate surrounding the concept of law», just as it exemplarily solves its controversies [4 , p. 5].

  6. I’ll use here some general formulations by Charles Taylor [35].

  7. «Constitutional review claims to be closer than the parliament to the ideal dimension of law…» [3, p. 272].

  8. I’m naturally invoking the main topics of our Poznan’s meeting.

  9. This dominant methodic paradigm is evidently the one that 19th Century’s normativistic formalism (and rule conceptualism) has been able to construct : a conception of law and legal thought we could identify (in its spectrum of institutionalizing possibilities) invoking (as exemplary reflexive synthetesis) Jhering’s «Theorie der juristischen Technik» and Langdell’s «system of classification».

  10. To say it respectively with Bernard Jackson and Stanley Fish.

  11. «Law is better regarded as a servant of social need, a conception that severs the law from any inherent dependence on its past…» [32, p. 159].

  12. Those leading hetero-references become explicit in academic and social movements such as Law and Economics, Feminist Jurisprudence(s), Critical Race Theory and other narrative critical jurisprudences, law as musical and dramatic performance, law and culture (without forgetting some trends in Law and Literature scholarship).

  13. This return will privilege however, certainly not by chance, some of Habermas’ well-known formulations.

  14. These formulations are used by Habermas in his answers to Giovanna Borradori about the dangers of a «return to the exclusivity of premodern belief attitudes» [8, pp. 31–32].

  15. For a reconstitution of this «decentring», see specially 15, volume I, pp. 164 ff., 441 ff., 455–460, volume II, pp. 179 e ff., 209 ff., 225–227, 270 ff., 413 ff., 571–593.

  16. An eloquent use of this counterpoint (denouncing «the affirmative stance toward social modernity and the denigration of cultural modernity») is developed by Habermas in «Neoconservative culture criticism…» [7, pp. 81 ff.].

  17. These formulae are by Günther Ellsheid [13 , pp. 232–233]. «Der Methodendualismus versteht Sein im Sinne von Faktizität, während der (…) Methodenmonismus Sein als Wesenwirkung begreift» [13, p. 233].

  18. The indispensable development is certainly in Habermas’ «Wahrheitstheorien» [14, pp. 211 ff.].

  19. I shall not consider here the important differences that, concerning «human rights» (defending respectively its «moral» and its «juridical» nature), separate Alexy and Habermas. I’ve explored these differences in «O homo humanus do direito e o projecto inacabado da modernidade» (to be published soon).

  20. The formulations quoted are all from Habermas, «Questions and Counterquestions» [7, pp. 212–216].

  21. This understanding of law’s constitutive cultural-civilizational originarium (which will now be explored) has been eloquently defended and developed by Castanheira Neves [28, passim, 29, pp. 111 ff. (III), 30, pp. 7–10 (II)].

  22. The formulation is by Georges Steiner, although Steiner is certainly not considering here the Roman invention of law, but the different contributions of «Greek thinking» and «Judaic morality» [34, p. 53].

  23. «Unter ihrem Namen wird die Humanitas zum ersten Mal bedacht und erstrebt…» [21], p. 19).

  24. I cite here the specific conception of the legal system proposed by Castanheira Neves [26, pp. 78–81, 152–157, 188–196, 278–283(ßß) and 27, pp. 95 ff.].

  25. The formula is by Simmonds [33, pp. 37 ff («Law as Instrument and as Aspiration»].

References

  1. Alexy, Robert. 1999. A defense of Radbruch’s formula. In Recrafting the rule of law. The limits of legal order, ed. David Dyzenhaus, 15–39. Oxford/Portland Oregon: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Alexy, Robert. 1999. Begriff und Geltung des Rechts. Freiburg/München: Karl Albert Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Alexy, Robert. 2009. The dual nature of law. In IVR 24th world congress’s papers (Plenary Sessions), Beijing 15–20 September 2009 (Global Harmony and Rule of Law), 257–274 [Now in Ratio Juris, 23 (2): 167–182].

  4. Alexy, Robert. 2010. The argument from injustice. A reply to legal positivism. New York: paperback edition, Oxford University Press [Translation of Begriff und Geltung des Rechts (1994)].

  5. Balkin, Jack, and Sanford Levinson. 2000. Legal canons: An introduction. In Legal canons, ed. Levinson Balkin, 3–44. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Balkin, Jack, and Sanford Levinson. 2006. Law and humanities: An uneasy relationship. Yale Journal of Law & The Humanities 18: 155–187.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Bernstein, Richard (ed.). 1985. Habermas and modernity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Borradori, Giovanna. 2003. Philosophy in a time of terror: Dialogues with Jurgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Coleman, Jules. 2001. The practice of principle. In defence of a pragmatist approach to legal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Douzinas, Costas, and Ronnie Warrington. 1991. Postmodern jurisprudence: The law of text in the texts of law. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Douzinas, Costas, and Ronnie Warrington. 1994. Justice miscarried. Ethics, aesthetics and the law. New York/London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Fuller, Leon. 1969. The morality of law. London: revised edition, Yale University Press.

  13. Ellsheid, Günther. 1994. Das Naturrechtsproblem. Eine systematische Orientierung. In Einführung in Rechtsphilosophie und Rechtstheorie der Gegenwart, ed. Kaufmann and Hassemer, 179–247. Heidelberg: 6. Auflage, Müller.

  14. Fahrenbach, Helmut (ed.). 1982. Wirklichkeit und Reflexion. Walter Schulz zum 60. Geburtstag. Stuttgart: Neske.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Habermas, Jürgen. 1981. Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns 2. Bände. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Habermas, Jürgen. 1983. Moralbewußtsein und kommunikatives Handeln. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Habermas, Jürgen. 1992. Faktizität und Geltung. Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Habermas, Jürgen. 1996, pocket edition 1999. Die Einbeziehung des Anderen. Studien zur politischen Theorie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag.

  19. Habermas, Jürgen. 1998. Die postnationale Konstellation. Politische Essays. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Habermas, Jürgen. 2004. Der gespaltene Westen. Kleine politischen Schriften X. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Heidegger, Martin. 1947. Über den Humanismus. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Howarth, David. 2000. On the question ‘What Is Law?’. Res Publica 6(3): 259–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Kramer, Matthew. 2004. Where law and morality meet. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Levinas, Emmanuel. 1991. Entre nous. Essais sur le penser-à-l′autre. Paris: pocket edition, Grasset & Pasquelle.

  25. Levinas, Emmanuel. 2004. Autrement qu’être ou au-delà de l’essence (La Haye, 1978). Paris: Pocket edition, Kluwer.

  26. Neves, António Castanheira. 1995. Metodologia Jurídica. Problemas Fundamentais. Coimbra: Coimbra Editora.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Neves, António Castanheira. 1995. A unidade de sistema jurídico: o seu problema e o seu sentido. In Digesta. Estudos acerca do direito, do pensamento jurídico, da sua metodologia e outros, vol II, 95–180. Coimbra: Coimbra Editora.

  28. Neves, António Castanheira. 2008. Coordenadas de uma reflexão sobre o problema universal do direito—ou as condições da emergência do direito como direito. In Digesta. Estudos acerca do direito, do pensamento jurídico, da sua metodologia e outros, vol III, 9–41. Coimbra: Coimbra Editora.

  29. Neves, António Castanheira. 2008. O problema da universalidade do direito – ou o direito hoje, na diferença e no encontro humano-dialogante das culturas. In Digesta. Estudos acerca do direito, do pensamento jurídico, da sua metodologia e outros, vol III, 101–128. Coimbra: Coimbra Editora.

  30. Neves, António Castanheira. 2009. Pensar o direito em tempo de perplexidade. In Liber Amicorum de José de Sousa e Brito em comemoração do 70º aniversário. Estudos de Direito e Filosofia, ed. João Lopes Alves et al., 3–28. Coimbra: Almedina.

  31. Pintore, Anna. 2000. Law without truth. Liverpool: Deborah Charles Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Posner, Richard. 2001. Frontiers of legal theory. Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Simmonds, Nigel. 2007. Law as a moral idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Steiner, Georges. 2006. The idea of Europe, quoted in the Portuguese translation A ideia da Europa, Lisboa: 3ª ed.,Gradiva.

  35. Taylor, Charles. 1989. Inwardness and the culture of modernity. In Zwischenbetractungen im Prozess der Aufklärung. Jürgen Habermas zum 60. Geburtstag, ed. Honneth, McCarthy, Offe, Wellmer, 601–623. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1989.

  36. White, James Boyd. 1985. Heracles’ bow. Essays on the rethoric and poetics of the law. Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. White, James Boyd. 1990. Justice as translation. An essay in cultural and legal criticism. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to José Manuel Aroso Linhares.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Aroso Linhares, J.M. Law’s Cultural Project and the Claim to Universality or the Equivocalities of a Familiar Debate. Int J Semiot Law 25, 489–503 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-011-9233-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-011-9233-x

Keywords

Navigation