Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Explanation and the Nature of Scientific Knowledge

  • Article
  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Explaining phenomena is a primary goal of science. Consequently, it is unsurprising that gaining a proper understanding of the nature of explanation is an important goal of science education. In order to properly understand explanation, however, it is not enough to simply consider theories of the nature of explanation. Properly understanding explanation requires grasping the relation between explanation and understanding, as well as how explanations can lead to scientific knowledge. This article examines the nature of explanation, its relation to understanding, and how explanations are used to generate scientific knowledge via inferences to the best explanation. Studying these features and applications of explanation not only provides insight into a concept that is important for science education in its own right, but also sheds light on an aspect of recent debates concerning the so-called consensus view of nature of science (NOS). Once the relation between explanation, understanding, and knowledge is clear, it becomes apparent that science is unified in important ways. Seeing this unification provides some support for thinking that there are general features of NOS of the sort proposed by the consensus view and that teaching about these general features of NOS should be a goal of science education.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although this is widely held, it is not universally so. Theorists sympathetic to constructive empiricism, such as van Fraassen (1980, 1989), are apt to maintain that the primary aim of science is to construct theories that simply fit the observable phenomena—explanations that go beyond what is observable are superfluous at best and epistemically unacceptable at worst. Two points are worth keeping in mind here though. First, the primacy of explanation in science and science education is widely endorsed in science education reform documents. Take the National Research Council’s (2012) framework for K-12 science education, for example. This framework consists of three dimensions: scientific and engineering practices, crosscutting concepts, and disciplinary core ideas. Explanation figures prominently in the first two of these three dimensions. It is similarly emphasized in other education reform documents such as AAAS (1993), National Research Council (1996, 2007), and NGSS (2013). Second, constructive empiricists themselves recognize that explanation is important—they simply claim that the goal of such explanations is only to adequately describe the observable world, not to give us knowledge of theoretical entities. So, even constructive empiricists, who deny that explanation is the primary aim of science, can agree that explanation is important.

  2. For the results of some of these clinical studies, see Gopnik (1998), Gopnik and Glymour (2002), Gopnik et al. (2004), Gopnik and Sobel (2000), and Steyvers et al (2003).

  3. Philosophers with very diverse views on the nature of explanation and understanding agree that the two are closely linked with explanation providing a means to achieving understanding. See, for example, Achinstein (1983), de Regt (2009, 2013), de Regt and Dieks (2005), Friedman (1974), Harman (1986), Khalifa (2012), Khalifa and Gadomski (2013), Kim (1994), Kitcher (1981, 2002), Kvanvig (2003), Lewis (1986), Lipton (2004), Moser (1989), Railton (1993), Salmon (1984, 1998), Sober (1983), Strevens (2006, 2013), Trout (2002), van Fraassen (1980), von Wright (1971), Wilkenfeld (2013, 2014), and Woodward (2003). Even Hempel (1965) and Hempel and Oppenheim (1948), who thought that understanding was too subject dependent to be a proper focus of philosophical study, agree that explanations provide understanding.

  4. This is one of the major criticisms that some press against String Theory. For discussion of this criticism, see Dawid (2013).

  5. In some ways, this view may be a bit simplistic. As we will see later, one might think that explanation and prediction are very similar (perhaps even the same—one is simply backward looking in time and the other forward looking). Also, it is reasonable to think that making predictions is a factor that can make one explanation better than another. So, the relationship between explanation and prediction is not completely clear-cut. However, for the present purpose we can treat them as separate in which case explanation is primary.

  6. Strevens (2013) argues that when it comes to science understanding can only be achieved via explanations, i.e., scientific understanding without explanation is impossible. de Regt (2009), Gijsbers (2013), Hindriks (2013), and Lipton (2009) disagree. It is worth noting that even though they argue that it is possible to gain understanding without having an explanation, none of these philosophers contest the claim that we typically come to have understanding via explanations or the claim that providing understanding is the goal of producing explanations.

  7. Sometimes “NOS” is used in such a way that it refers to only nature of scientific knowledge, and at other times “NOS” is used to refer to both nature of scientific knowledge and scientific inquiry. Throughout this article, “NOS” will be used to refer to only nature of scientific knowledge.

  8. This view, which is sometimes referred to as the “consensus view,” is largely the result of work by Norman Lederman along with his various collaborators. See, for example, Abd-El-Khalick (2004), Bell (2004), Cobern and Loving (2001), Flick and Lederman (2004), Hanuscin et al. (2006), Khishfe and Lederman (2006), Lederman (1999, 2007), Lederman and Niess (1997), McComas et al. (1998), McComas and Olson (1998), Osborne et al. (2003), Schwartz and Lederman (2008), Smith and Scharmann (1999), and Ziedler et al. (2002).

  9. See Allchin (2011), Elby and Hammer (2001), Irzik and Nola (2011, 2014), Rudolph (2000), van Dijk (2011, 2014), and Erduran and Dagher (2014).

  10. For support of this claim see AAAS (1993), Mortimer and Scott (2003), National Research Council (1996, 2007, 2012), and Osborne and Dillon (2008).

  11. For a sampling of some of the major theories of the nature of explanation see Braithwaite (1953), Friedman (1974), Gardiner (1959), Hempel (1942, 1965), Hempel and Oppenheim (1948), Kitcher (1981, 1989), Nagel (1961), Popper (1959), Salmon (1971, 1984, 1990), Strevens (2008), and Woodward (2003).

  12. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this way of expressing the distinction between explanation and explaining.

  13. Two notable exceptions to this majority opinion are Achinstein (1983) and van Fraassen (1980). Both of these philosophers hold that explanation cannot exist without acts of communication.

  14. Strevens (2008) endorses this general conception of explanation as well.

  15. Admittedly, one might think that in order to have a “real” explanation one needs to provide information about causal dependence relations or information about natural laws governing the dependence relations in question. Two points about this concern are worth keeping in mind. First, insofar as it is plausible to think that there are genuine explanations in pure mathematics it is unclear that such restrictions are necessary. For an overview of reasons for and against thinking there are genuine explanations in pure mathematics, see Mancosu (2011). Second, the addition of such restrictions would not affect the points made in this paper. So, the reader is welcome to understand the account of explanation here as having such restrictions, if she believes they are necessary for genuine explanations.

  16. For a discussion of these issues, see Franklin (1981).

  17. It is worth noting that most philosophers agree with Trout that this sort of “aha” experience is neither necessary nor sufficient for possessing genuine understanding. However, several philosophers have argued that Trout’s arguments concerning this phenomenal sense of understanding do not undermine the importance of understanding as an aim of science or a goal of everyday explanations (de Regt 2004, 2009; Grimm 2009; Lipton 2009). Some (Lipton 2009; Grimm 2009) go so far as to argue that the “aha” experience may not be as misleading as Trout suggests, and it may in fact be a reliable guide to the presence of genuine understanding in some cases.

  18. Although we tend to have an intuitive grasp of the notion, clearly defining “positive epistemic status” is difficult. Perhaps the best way to understand this notion is by noting other familiar states that have positive epistemic status such as rational beliefs and knowledge on the one hand and states that lack positive epistemic status such as mere opinions, beliefs arising from wishful thinking, and guesses on the other hand. The idea that understanding is a cognitive achievement (a mental state with positive epistemic status) is widespread; see Elgin (1996, 2007), Grimm (2001, 2006, 2014a, b), Khalifa (2011, 2012, 2013), Khalifa and Gadomski (2013), Kvanvig (2003, 2009), Pritchard (2009, 2014), Wilkenfeld (2013), and Zagzebski (2001).

  19. Strevens (2013) draws a similar distinction between what he calls “understanding why” and “understanding with.” The former corresponds to de Regt’s UP, while the latter corresponds to his UT.

  20. Plausibly, one way of understanding the distinction between UP and UT is in terms of their objects. The object of UP is natural phenomena; the object of UT is abstract content (theories).

  21. There is at least one other important sense of understanding, which is often characterized as “understanding-that.” For example, Ted understands that the theory of relativity says X. While this sort of understanding is important, we will not focus on it here. The primary reason for this is that ascriptions of this sort of understanding are widely held to simply be knowledge ascriptions (see Kvanvig 2009; Pritchard 2009). For instance, when we say, “Ted understands that the theory of relativity says X” all we are saying is that “Ted knows that the theory of relativity says X.” While this sort of understanding is important, it is fairly clear that it is simply a precondition of UT. One cannot have the ability to use a theory to construct explanations without knowing what the theory says. So, for present purposes we can assume that individuals have this sort of understanding of the theories in question.

  22. These two very different understandings of the nature of theories, the ordinary and the scientific, may be partly to blame for some of the misguided objections to evolution such as the “it is just a theory” objection. For more on this and other misguided objections to evolution, see McCain and Weslake (2013). See Kampourakis (2014) for an in-depth discussion of some of the common misunderstandings that lead to resistance against accepting evolutionary theory.

  23. See National Research Council (2012) for a similar account of scientific theories. Of course, there are important issues concerning how we should understand the fundamental nature of scientific theories. It is not clear whether theories are best understood as ultimately collections of axiomatized sentences or nonlinguistic models, or both. Fortunately, for present purposes, it is not necessary to settle the debate concerning the fundamental ontology of scientific theories. For more on this, see Winther (2015).

  24. Plausibly, using a theory to make predictions about phenomena is simply an aspect of constructing explanations. After all, if explanations amount to information about dependence relations, then they allow one to make predictions about what will happen as well as to explain what has happened—explanation and prediction are simply backward looking (explanations) and forward looking (predictions) approaches to the same dependence relations. For this reason, we will focus primarily on explanation and the role that it plays in UT and UP. If one is convinced that explanation and prediction are not this closely connected, then she can construe the current discussion of UT in terms of the ability to construct explanations and the ability to make predictions.

  25. Both UT and UP come in degrees. One might have a greater or lesser degree of UT and so understand a particular phenomenon that is explained by the relevant theory to a greater or lesser degree. In the text, we are considering the high end of the scale of UT—being able to construct explanations of phenomena requires a fairly significant degree of UT. This level of UT is something to strive for as an educational goal, but it is good to keep in mind that one can exhibit UT and UP without reaching this highest level. For example, one might have UT of a theory and UP of phenomena by being able to appreciate explanations of phenomena that are provided by a particular theory without being able to come up with such explanations on her own.

  26. Similar considerations apply to our knowledge of the explanatory hypotheses generated from theories and our knowledge of laws of nature.

  27. Here, we are concerned with the sort of knowledge that is gained in a particular scientific context—how a theorist can come to know that a particular theory is true.

  28. IBE is sometimes referred to as “abduction.” It is best to use separate terminology because there are good reasons for thinking that IBE and abduction are not the same. See Hintikka (1998) and Minnameier (2004) for arguments to this effect.

  29. See Lycan (1988) for a similar, but different formulation. The primary difference is that Lycan’s (1988) formulation has the conclusion that “[probably] H is true” instead of “H is true.”

  30. See Beebe (2009), Kuhn (1977), Lacey (2005), Lipton (2004), Longino (1990), Lycan (1988), McAllister (1996), McMullin (1982), Quine and Ullian (1978), Thagard (1978), and Vogel (1990) for a sampling of the explanatory virtues that have been proposed in various scientific contexts and the literature on the nature of explanation. Some might question whether the virtues listed are distinct—for example, some claim that predictive power is what separates ad hoc theories from those that are not (Popper 1959; Psillos 1999). So, they might question whether predictive power and non-ad hocness are actually two virtues rather than the same thing. Fortunately, for our purposes it is sufficient to simply have a grasp of what some of the most commonly cited explanatory virtues are.

  31. For more on this, see Lipton (2004).

  32. This picture of scientific knowledge is developed in much greater detail in McCain (2016).

  33. It is worth noting that several of these examples of IBE from the history of science could be beneficial to cover in a classroom setting. For example, the discovery of Neptune nicely illustrates the struggle to deal with anomalous data. It also provides an exemplar of how explanatory reasoning can be used to make predictions and new discoveries. Additionally, discussion of Darwin’s arguments in support of evolution could help illustrate why evolutionary theory is so well supported. It could also show students how a theory can be well supported by being the best explanation of a large and diverse set of data.

  34. This claim is somewhat controversial because some think that appeal to likelihood ratios alone may be the key to medical diagnosis. Although it is plausible that likelihood ratios can be important tools in medical diagnosis (see Grimes and Schulz 2005), it is not clear that even their use cannot be accounted for under the umbrella of IBE. For present purposes, it is enough to note that it has been claimed that IBE is the primary method of medical diagnosis, and this claim has some plausibility.

  35. Conee and Feldman (2008), Goodman (1965, 1978), Harman (1973, 1986), Lycan (1988, 2012), McCain (2013, 2014), Moser (1989), Poston (2014), and Sellars (1963) each defend explanationist theories of justification.

  36. Despite its widespread use in science and everyday life, IBE is not without its critics. See van Fraassen (1989), Ladyman et al. (1997), Roche and Sober (2013), and Wray (2008). One of the lines of criticism that many find particularly troubling is the claim that IBE leads to probabilistic incoherence. In other words, critics charge that IBE is inconsistent with accepted theories of probabilistic reasoning such as Bayesianism. For a survey of responses to objections to IBE, see Douven (2011). For responses to the claim that IBE runs afoul of probabilistic reasoning, see Lipton (2004), McCain and Poston (2014), McGrew (2003), Okasha (2000), Psillos (1999), and Weisberg (2009). Some (Huemer 2009; Poston 2014) even go so far as to argue that without IBE probabilistic reasoning, including Bayesian confirmation theory, straightforwardly falls prey to the skeptical problem of induction.

  37. It is worth noting that various studies have yielded empirical support for the consensus view and for the benefits of teaching this view. For discussion, see Driver et al. (1996), Feng Deng et al. (2011), Khishfe and Lederman (2006), Lederman (2007), and Lederman et al. (2013).

  38. For particularly clear expressions of the consensus view, see Lederman (1999), Schwartz and Lederman (2008), and Irzik and Nola (2011).

  39. See Schwartz et al. (2012) for reasons to think that these criticisms, particularly those of Allchin, are not grounded in the available empirical data.

  40. Matthews (2015) also presses this criticism of the consensus view.

  41. van Dijk (2014) reaffirms her earlier critical stance toward the consensus view.

  42. See Abd-El-Khalick (2012) for a different line of response to these sorts of criticisms. Essentially, Abd-El-Khalick offers good reasons for doubting that critics have really made a case for their claims against the consensus view. This differs from the response that we have developed here because here we have reasons arising from the connections between explanation, understanding, and knowledge for thinking the consensus view is correct, and so for thinking these criticisms are mistaken.

  43. Of course, this is not to say that there are no differences in our reasoning in ordinary life and our reasoning in scientific contexts. As we have already noted, in scientific contexts our reasoning tends to be much more precise and rigorous. Plus, there are reasons to think that probabilistic reasoning is handled much more accurately in scientific contexts than in our ordinary life. See Gilovich (1991), Kahneman et al. (1982), Nisbett and Ross (1980), Plous (1993), Tversky and Kahneman (1983), and Tweney et al. (1981) for discussions of the sorts of errors in probabilistic reasoning we are prone to in ordinary life.

  44. Even critics of the consensus view, such as Irzik and Nola (2011, 2014), seem to accept that there is a great deal of unity to the sciences. Plausibly, it is for this reason that they propose a family resemblance approach as a holistic and unified way of understanding NOS. Erduran and Dagher (2014) also support the family resemblance approach as a method of properly capturing the unified nature of science. Although we have seen that exploring IBE and the nature of explanation gives good reasons for thinking that there is more unity to the sciences than mere family resemblances, the family resemblance approach is worth taking seriously for at least two reasons. First, as already noted, the family resemblance approach helps to emphasize that the view that science is “disunified by its very nature” is misguided. Second, this approach may be useful in making progress in solving the demarcation problem, which is largely left untouched by the present proposal. For alternative approaches to solving this problem, see the essays collected in Pigliucci and Boudry (2013).

  45. It is worth emphasizing that we do not always need to appeal to laws in order to provide an explanation. In everyday contexts, we seldom appeal to natural laws to explain phenomena. Even in scientific contexts, we do not always appeal to a natural law in order to generate an explanation, though we often do.

  46. This is a useful contribution to the already significant support that has been garnered for the consensus view of NOS. See the following for a sampling of this support: Abd-El-Khalick (2004), Bell (2004), Cobern and Loving (2001), Flick and Lederman (2004), Hanuscin et al. (2006), Khishfe and Lederman (2006), McComas et al. (1998), McComas and Olson (1998), Osborne et al. (2003), Schwartz and Lederman (2008), Smith and Scharmann (1999), and Ziedler et al. (2002).

  47. Constructing explanations and evaluating competing explanations (IBE) are desired cognitive outcomes according to several science education reform documents. See, for example, National Research Council (2007, 2012) and NGSS (2013).

  48. The parenthetical remarks were added to the quote in order to emphasize the connections with the present discussion.

  49. Some even go so far as to claim that a general facility in generating and using explanations is more important than domain-specific knowledge (Schank 2011).

  50. For a nice illustration of how this can be done, see McComas and Kampourakis (2015).

  51. For a more extensive defense of the consensus view of NOS and an articulation of how an understanding of various epistemological issues strengthens its foundation, see McCain (2016).

References

  • AAAS (American Association for the Advancement of Science). (1989). Science for all Americans: A project 2061 report on literacy goals in science, mathematics, and technology. Washington, D.C.: AAAS.

    Google Scholar 

  • AAAS (American Association for the Advancement of Science). (1993). Benchmarks for science literacy. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abd-El-Khalick, F. (2004). Over and over and over again: College students’ views of nature of science. In L. B. Flick & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Scientific inquiry and nature of science (pp. 389–426). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abd-El-Khalick, F. (2012). Examining the sources for our understandings about science: Enduring conflations and critical issues in research on nature of science in science education. International Journal of Science Education, 34, 353–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Achinstein, P. (1983). The nature of explanation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Achinstein, P. (2001). The book of evidence. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adler, J. (1994). Testimony, trust, knowing. Journal of Philosophy, 91, 264–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2011). Evaluating knowledge of the nature of (whole) science. Science Education, 95, 518–542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J. (2009). The abductivist reply to skepticism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 605–636.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, R. (2004). Perusing Pandora’s box: Exploring the what, when, and how of nature of science. In L. B. Flick & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Scientific inquiry and nature of science (pp. 427–446). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1981). Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology. PSA, 1980(2), 613–662.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1984). The current status of scientific realism. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 41–82). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braaten, M., & Windschitl, M. (2011). Working toward a stronger conceptualization of scientific explanation for science education. Science Education, 95, 639–669.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite, R. (1953). Scientific explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, W. F., Chinn, C. A., & Samarapungavan, A. (2000). Explanation in scientists and children. In F. Keil & R. A. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 279–298). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobern, W., & Loving, C. (2001). Defining ‘‘Science’’ in a multicultural world: Implications for science education. Science Education, 85, 50–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2008). Evidence. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays (pp. 83–104). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859/1962). The origin of species. New York, NY: Collier.

  • Dascal, M. (1979). Conversational relevance. In A. Margalit (Ed.), Meaning and use (pp. 153–174). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawid, R. (2013). String theory and the scientific method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2004). Discussion note: Making sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 71, 98–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2009). Understanding and scientific explanation. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 21–42). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2013). Understanding and explanation: Living apart together? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 505–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese, 144, 137–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2011). Abduction. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/abduction/

  • Driver, R., Leach, J., Millar, R., & Scott, P. (1996). Young peoples’s images of science. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1934). On the method of theoretical physics. Philosophy of Science, 1, 163–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elby, A., & Hammer, D. (2001). On the substance of a sophisticated epistemology. Science Education, 85, 554–567.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (1996). Considered judgment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2007). Understanding and the facts. Philosophical Studies, 132, 33–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D., & Schechter, J. (2008). How are basic belief-forming methods justified? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76, 547–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erduran, S., & Dagher, Z. (2014). Reconceptualizing the nature of science for science education: Scientific knowledge, practices and other family categories. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feng Deng, D. C., Tsai, C., & Chai, C. S. (2011). Student’s views of the nature of science: A critical review of research. Science Education, 95, 961–999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flick, L. B., & Lederman, N. G. (2004). Introduction. In L. B. Flick & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Scientific inquiry and nature of science (pp. ix–xviii). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Franklin, R. L. (1981). Knowledge, belief and understanding. Philosophical Quarterly, 31, 193–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (1994). Against gullibility. In B. K. Matilal & A. Chakrabarti (Eds.), Knowing from words (pp. 125–161). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, P. (1959). The nature of historical explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauch, H. G, Jr. (1992). Statistical analysis of regional yield trials: AMMI analysis of factorial designs. New York, NY: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauch, H. G, Jr. (2012). Scientific method in brief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gijsbers, V. (2013). Understanding, explanation, and unification. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 516–522.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T. (1991). How we know what isn’t so: The fallibility of human reason in everyday life. New York, NY: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (1984). Explanation and realism. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 173–192). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1965). Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (1998). Explanation as orgasm. Minds and Machines, 8, 101–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Glymour, C. (2002). Causal maps and Bayes nets: A cognitive and computational account of theory formation. In P. Carruthers, S. Stich, & M. Siegal (Eds.), The cognitive basis of science (pp. 117–132). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., Glymour, C., Sobel, D., Schulz, L., Kushnir, T., & Danks, D. (2004). A theory of causal learning in children: Causal maps and Bayes nets. Psychology Review, 111, 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Sobel, D. (2000). Detecting blickets: How young children use information about novel causal powers in categorization and induction. Child Development, 71, 1205–1222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimes, D. A., & Schulz, K. F. (2005). Refining clinical diagnosis with likelihood ratios. The Lancet, 365, 1500–1505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2001). Ernest Sosa, knowledge, and understanding. Philosophical Studies, 106, 171–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2006). Is understanding a species of knowledge? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 515–535.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2009). Reliability and the sense of understanding. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 83–99). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2014a). Understanding. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 84–94). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2014b). Understanding as knowledge of causes. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue epistemology naturalized: Bridges between virtue epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 329–346). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanuscin, D. L., Akerson, V. L., & Phillipson-Mower, T. (2006). Integrating nature of science instruction into a physical science content course for preservice elementary teachers: NOS views of teaching assistants. Science Education, 90, 912–935.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1986). Varieties of realism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1942). The function of general laws in history. Journal of Philosophy, 39, 35–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York, NY: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. (2013). Explanation, understanding, and unrealistic models. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 523–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy, 34, 503–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, J. R. (2004). Abduction in natural language understanding. In L. Horn & G. Ward (Eds.), The handbook of pragmatics (pp. 724–741). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2009). Explanationist aid for the theory of inductive logic. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 60, 345–375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G., & Nola, R. (2011). A family resemblance approach to the nature of science for science education. Science & Education, 20, 591–607.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G., & Nola, R. (2014). New directions for nature of science research. In M. Matthews (Ed.), International handbook of research in history, philosophy and science teaching (pp. 999–1021). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, M. (2002). Reconsidering a scientific revolution: The case of Einstein versus Lorentz. Physics in Perspective, 4, 421–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J. R., & Josephson, G. S. (Eds.). (1994). Abductive inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. (2014). Understanding evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (2011). Science starts early. Science, 331, 1022–1023.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C., & Wilson, R. A. (2000). Explaining explanation. In F. Keil & R. A. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 1–18). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2011). Understanding, knowledge, and scientific antirealism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 83, 93–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2012). Inaugurating understanding or repackaging explanation? Philosophy of Science, 79, 15–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2013). Understanding, grasping, and luck. Episteme, 10, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K., & Gadomski, M. (2013). Understanding as explanatory knowledge: The case of Bjorken scaling. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 384–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khishfe, R., & Lederman, N. G. (2006). Teaching nature of science within a controversial topic: Integrated versus nonintegrated. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 43, 395–418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1994). Explanatory knowledge and metaphysical dependence. Philosophical Issues, 5, 51–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48, 507–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13, 410–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2002). Scientific knowledge. In P. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 385–407). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2009). The value of understanding. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value (pp. 95–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (2005). Is science value free? Values and scientific understanding (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., & van Fraassen, B. C. (1997). A defence of van Fraassen’s critique of abductive inference: Reply to Psillos. Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 305–321.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (1999). Teachers’ understanding of the nature of science and classroom practice: Factors that facilitate or impede the relationship. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 36, 916–929.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (2007). Nature of science: Past, present, and future. In S. K. Abell & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Handbook of research on science education (pp. 831–879). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G., Lederman, J. S., & Antink, A. (2013). Nature of science and scientific inquiry as contexts for the learning of science and achievement of scientific literacy. International Journal of Education in Mathematics, Science and Technology, 1, 138–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G., & Niess, M. L. (1997). The nature of science: Naturally? School Science and Mathematics, 97, 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (2000). Theory of knowledge (2nd ed.). Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Causal explanation. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 214–240). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1998). The epistemology of testimony. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2009). Understanding without explanation. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 43–63). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (2002). Explanation and epistemology. In P. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 408–433). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (2012). Explanationist rebuttals (coherentism defended again). Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50, 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (2011). Explanation in mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/mathematics-explanation/

  • Matthews, M. (2015). Science teaching: The contribution of history and philosophy of science (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, J. W. (1996). Beauty and revolution in science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2013). Explanationist evidentialism. Episteme, 10, 299–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2014). Evidentialism and epistemic justification. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2016). The nature of scientific knowledge: An epistemological approach. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • McCain, K., & Poston, T. (2014). Why explanatoriness is evidentially relevant. Thought, 3, 145–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K., & Weslake, B. (2013). Evolutionary theory and the epistemology of science. In K. Kampourakis (Ed.), The philosophy of biology: A companion for educators (pp. 101–119). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F., Clough, M. P., & Almazroa, H. (1998). The role and character of the nature of science in science education. In W. F. McComas (Ed.), The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies (pp. 3–40). Hingham: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F., & Kampourakis, K. (2015). Using the history of biology, chemistry, geology, and physics to illustrate general aspects of nature of science. Review of Science, Mathematics and ICT Education, 9, 47–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F., & Olson, J. K. (1998). The nature of science in international science education standards documents. In W. F. McComas (Ed.), The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies (pp. 41–52). Hingham: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrew, T. (2003). Confirmation, heuristics, and explanatory reasoning. British, Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 553–567.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1982). Values in science. PSA, 1982(2), 3–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1992). The inference that makes science. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minnameier, G. (2004). Peirce-suit of truth—Why inference to the best explanation and abduction ought not to be confused. Erkenntnis, 60, 75–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mortimer, E., & Scott, P. (2003). Meaning making in secondary science classrooms. Philadelphia, PA: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. K. (1989). Knowledge and evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science: Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council. (1996). National science education standards. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council. (2007). Taking science to school: Learning and teaching science in grades K-8. Committee on Science Learning, Kindergarten through Eighth Grade. R. A. Duschl, H. A. Schweingruber, & A. W. Shouse (Eds.), Board on Science Education, Center for Science Education, Division of Behavioral and Social Sciences and Education. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

  • National Research Council. (2012). A framework for K-12 science education: Practices, crosscutting concepts, and core ideas. Committee on a Conceptual Framework for New K-12 Science Education Standards. Board on Science Education, Division of Behavioral and Social Sciences and Education. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

  • Newton, I. (1687/1999). The Principia: Mathematical principles of natural philosophy (I. B. Cohen & A. Whitman, Trans.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

  • NGSS Lead States. (2013). Next generation science standards: For states, by states. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of social judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2000). Van Fraassen’s critique of inference to the best explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 31, 691–710.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J., Collins, S., Ratcliffe, M., Millar, R., & Duschl, R. (2003). What ‘‘Ideas-about-Science’’ should be taught in school science? A Delphi study of the expert community. Journal of Research in Science Education, 40, 692–720.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J., & Dillon, J. (2008). Science education in Europe: Critical reflections. London: King’s College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., & Boudry, M. (Eds.). (2013). Philosophy of pseudoscience: Reconsidering the demarcation problem. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, J. C. (1988). Galileo, rationality and explanation. Philosophy of Science, 55, 87–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plous, S. (1993). The psychology of judgment and decision making. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poston, T. (2014). Reason & explanation: A defense of explanatory coherentism. New York: Palgrave-MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge, understanding and epistemic value. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Epistemology: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64 (pp. 19–44). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2014). Knowledge and understanding. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue epistemology naturalized: Bridges between virtue epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 315–328). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. S. (1978). The web of belief (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1993). Probability, explanation, and information. In D. H. Ruben (Ed.), Explanation (pp. 160–181). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W., & Sober, E. (2013). Explanatoriness is evidentially irrelevant, or inference to the best explanation meets Bayesian confirmation theory. Analysis, 73, 659–668.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2012). Philosophy of science: A contemporary introduction (3rd ed.). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudolph, J. L. (2000). Reconsidering the ‘nature of science’ as a curriculum component. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 32, 403–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1971). Statistical explanation. In W. Salmon (Ed.), Statistical explanation and statistical relevance (pp. 29–87). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1990). Four decades of scientific explanation. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1998). Causality and explanation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R. C. (2011). Teaching minds: How cognitive science can save our schools. New York, NY: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1954). Nature and the Greeks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, R., & Lederman, N. G. (2008). What scientists say: Scientists’ views of nature of science and relation to science context. International Journal of Science Education, 30, 727–771.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, R., Lederman, N. G., & Abd-El-Khalick, F. (2012). A series of misrepresentations: A response to Allchin’s whole approach to assessing nature of science understandings. Science Education, 96, 685–692.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Science, perception and reality. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. U., & Scharmann, L. C. (1999). Defining versus describing the nature of science: A pragmatic analysis for classroom teachers and science educators. Science Education, 83, 493–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1983). Equilibrium explanation. Philosophical Studies, 43, 201–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2015). Is the scientific method a myth? Perspectives from the history and philosophy of science. Metode, 5, 195–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steyvers, M., Tenenbaum, J., Wagenmakers, E., & Blum, B. (2003). Inferring causal networks from observations and interventions. Cognitive Science, 27, 453–489.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2006). Scientific explanation. In D. M. Borchert (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (2nd ed.). Detroit, MI: Macmillan Reference USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2013). No understanding without explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 510–515.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. R. (1978). The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice. Journal of Philosophy, 75, 76–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69, 212–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2005). Paying the price for a theory of explanation: De Regt’s discussion of Trout. Philosophy of Science, 72, 198–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2007). The psychology of scientific explanation. Philosophy Compass, 2, 564–591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90, 293–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweney, R., Doherty, M., & Mynatt, C. (1981). On scientific thinking. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, E. M. (2011). Portraying real science in science communication. Science Education, 95, 1086–1100.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, E. M. (2014). Understanding the heterogeneous nature of science: A comprehensive notion of PCK for scientific literacy. Science Education, 98, 397–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 658–666.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1971). Explanation and understanding. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2009). Locating IBE in the Bayesian framework. Synthese, 167, 125–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190, 997–1016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. (2014). Functional explaining: A new approach to the philosophy of explanation. Synthese, 191, 3367–3391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., & Keil, F. (2000). The shadows and shallows of explanation. In F. Keil & R. A. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 87–114). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. G. (2015). The structure of scientific theories. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/structure-scientific-theories/

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2014). Scientific explanation. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/scientific-explanation/

  • Wray, K. B. (2008). The argument from underconsideration as grounds for anti-realism: A defence. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22, 317–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2001). Recovering understanding. In M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty: Essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue (pp. 235–252). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziedler, D. N., Walker, K. A., & Ackett, W. A. (2002). Tangled up in views: Beliefs in the nature of science and responses to socioscientific dilemmas. Science Education, 86, 343–367.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to four anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and feedback on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kevin McCain.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McCain, K. Explanation and the Nature of Scientific Knowledge. Sci & Educ 24, 827–854 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-015-9775-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-015-9775-5

Keywords

Navigation