Skip to main content
Log in

When Science Studies Religion: Six Philosophy Lessons for Science Classes

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is an unfortunate fact of academic life that there is a sharp divide between science and philosophy, with scientists often being openly dismissive of philosophy, and philosophers being equally contemptuous of the naiveté of scientists when it comes to the philosophical underpinnings of their own discipline. In this paper I explore the possibility of reducing the distance between the two sides by introducing science students to some interesting philosophical aspects of research in evolutionary biology, using biological theories of the origin of religion as an example. I show that philosophy is both a discipline in its own right as well as one that has interesting implications for the understanding and practice of science. While the goal is certainly not to turn science students into philosophers, the idea is that both disciplines cannot but benefit from a mutual dialogue that starts as soon as possible, in the classroom.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Aoki, K. (1986). A stochastic model of gene-culture coevolution suggested by the “culture historical hypothesis” for the evolution of adult lactose absorption in humans. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 83, 2929–2933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A. (2003). Ernst Mayr’s ‘ultimate/proximate’ distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 553–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1998). The metaphysics. Translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

  • Berger, J. O., & Sellke, T. (1987). Testing a point null hypothesis: The irreconcilability of p values and evidence. Journal of American Statistical Association, 82, 112–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore, S. J. (2000). The meme machine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Blanke, O., Ortigue, S., Landis, T., & Seeck, M. (2002). Stimulating illusory own-body perceptions. Nature, 419, 269–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. (2008). Religion: Bound to believe? Nature, 455, 1038–1039.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I., & Love, A. (2008). Reductionism in biology. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/reduction-biology/.

  • Burnham, K. P., & Anderson, D. R. (2002). Model selection and multimodel inference: A practical information-theoretic approach. Berlin: Springer.

  • Chamberlin, T. C. (1890). The method of multiple working hypotheses. Science, 15, 92–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E. (2001). Historical science, experimental science, and the scientific method. Geology, 29, 987–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E. (2002). Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science. Philosophy of Science, 69, 474–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E. (2011). Prediction and explanation in historical natural science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, advanced online publication, 25 February 2011.

  • Cohen, J. (1994). The earth is round (p < .05). American Psychologist, 49, 997–1003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corfield, D., & Williamson, J. (2001). Foundations of Bayesianism. Berlin: Springer.

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection: Or, the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. London: John Murray.

  • Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The God delusion. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

  • De Pierris, G., & Friedman, M. (2008). Kant and Hume on causality. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/kant-hume-causality/.

  • Dennett, D. (1996). Darwins dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. New York: Simon and Schuster, p. 21.

  • Depew, D. (2008). Consequence etiology and biological teleology in Aristotle and darwin. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part C, 39, 379–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, M. W., & Laland, K. N. (1996). Gene-culture coevolutionary theory. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 11, 453–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flack, J. C., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2000). Any animal whatever: Darwinian building blocks of morality in monkeys and apes. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7, 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S. (2003). The split brain revisited. Scientific American, 287, 26–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B205, 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Vrba, E. S. (1982). Exaptation—a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology, 8, 4–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hone, W. D. E., Keesey, T. M., Pisani, D., & Purvis, A. (2005). Macroevolutionary trends in the Dinosauria: Cope’s rule. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 18, 587–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748/1952). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Forgotten Books.

  • Huxley, J. S. (1942/2010). Evolution: The modern synthesis. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Kant, I. (1783/2004). Prolegomena to any future metaphysics that will be able to come forward as science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kaplan, J. H. (2002). Historical evidence and human adaptation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S294–S304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, J. M., & Pigliucci, M. (2001). Genes ‘for’ phenotypes: A modern history view. Biology and Philosophy, 16, 189–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2002). Understanding philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). The methodology of scientific research programmes: Philosophical papers (Vol 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Manson, J. H., Perry, S., & Parish, A. R. (1997). Nonconceptive sexual behavior in bonobos and Capuchins. International Journal of Primatology, 18, 767–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology. Science, 134, 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newberg, A., D’Aquili, E., & Rause, V. (2002). Why God wont go away: Brain science and the biology of belief. New York: Random House.

  • Nix, T. W. & Barnette, J. J. (1998). The data analysis dilemma: Ban or abandon. A review of null hypothesis significance testing. Research in the Schools, 5, 3–14.

  • Norenzayan, A., & Shariff, A. F. (2008). The origin and evolution of religious prosociality. Science, 322, 58–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T., & Wong, H. Y. (2009). Emergent properties. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/properties-emergent/.

  • Okasha, S. (2006). Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Pigliucci, M. (2002). Denying evolution: Creationism, scientism, and the nature of science. Sunderland: Sinauer.

  • Pigliucci, M. (2003). From molecules to phenotypes?-The promise and limits of integrative biology. Basic and Applied Ecology, 4, 297–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., & Kaplan, J. (2000). The fall and rise of Dr. Pangloss: Adaptationism and the Spandrels paper 20 years later. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 15, 55–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., & Kaplan, J. (2006). Making sense of evolution: The conceptual foundations of evolutionary biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Price, G. R. (1970). Selection and covariance. Nature, 227, 520–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pyysiainen, I., & Hauser, M. (2009). The origins of religion: Evolved adaptation or by-product? Trends in Cognitive Science, 14, 104–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., & Newson, L. (2009). Is religion adaptive? Yes, no, neutral, but mostly we don’t know. In M. J. Murray & J. Schloss (Eds.), The believing primate: Scientific, philosophical and theological perspectives on the evolution of religion (pp. 100–117). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Rizzolatti, G. (2005). The mirror neuron system and its function in humans. Brain Structure & Function, 210, 419–421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schloss, J. (2009). Evolutionary theories of religion. Science unfettered or naturalism run wild? In M. J. Murray & J. Schloss (Eds.), The believing primate: Scientific, philosophical and theological perspectives on the evolution of religion (pp. 1–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Snow, C. P. (1993). The two cultures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1999). Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Weinberg, S. (1994). Against philosophy (pp. 166–190). In dreams of a final theory. New York: Vintage.

  • Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Williams, G. C. (1992). Natural selection: Domains, levels, and challenges. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1999). Consilience: The unity of knowledge. New York: Vintage.

  • Wilson, D. S. (2002). Darwin’s Cathedral: Evolution, religion, and the nature of society. University of Chicago Press: Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. S. (2007). Evolutionary religious studies (ERS): A Beginners guide. http://evolution.binghamton.edu/religion/resources/guide/.

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Massimo Pigliucci.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pigliucci, M. When Science Studies Religion: Six Philosophy Lessons for Science Classes. Sci & Educ 22, 49–67 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9355-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9355-2

Keywords

Navigation