Skip to main content
Log in

Explanation in Biology: Reduction, Pluralism, and Explanatory Aims

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This essay analyzes and develops recent views about explanation in biology. Philosophers of biology have parted with the received deductive-nomological model of scientific explanation primarily by attempting to capture actual biological theorizing and practice. This includes an endorsement of different kinds of explanation (e.g., mathematical and causal-mechanistic), a joint study of discovery and explanation, and an abandonment of models of theory reduction in favor of accounts of explanatory reduction. Of particular current interest are philosophical accounts of complex explanations that appeal to different levels of organismal organization and use contributions from different biological disciplines. The essay lays out one model that views explanatory integration across different disciplines as being structured by scientific problems. I emphasize the philosophical need to take the explanatory aims pursued by different groups of scientists into account, as explanatory aims determine whether different explanations are competing or complementary and govern the dynamics of scientific practice, including interdisciplinary research. I distinguish different kinds of pluralism that philosophers have endorsed in the context of explanation in biology, and draw several implications for science education, especially the need to teach science as an interdisciplinary and dynamic practice guided by scientific problems and explanatory aims.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Brigandt (2010c) presents a special notion of inference according to which explanations are inferences. However, this is not to deny the differences between predictions (arguments) and explanations, but to argue that what makes something a prediction or an explanation does not depend on its logical structure, but on the specific (empirical) content involved.

  2. This is well-reflected by the contemporary notion of the gene in molecular biology, which takes into account the complex and diverse processes in which DNA segments lead to different gene products, where this gene activity is highly context-dependent and generated by non-genetic factors (Brigandt 2010b; Stotz 2006a, b). Griffiths and Stotz (2007) call it the postgenomic molecular concept of the gene, as it stems from the postgenomic focus on genome wide gene function (beyond the mere study of the structure of individual DNA sequences).

  3. Heritable phenotypic variation can also result from epigenetic inheritance and niche construction. Moreover, given that heritable phenotypic variation is sufficient for evolutionary change, one may wonder whether it matters for evolutionary explanations what the basis of heritable phenotypic variation is (Godfrey-Smith 2009). I ignore these complications here, as my focus is on contrasting explanations of adaptation with explanations of evolvability.

  4. For a discussion of explanations focused on form and explanations focused on function in evolutionary biology, see Love (this issue).

  5. Explanatory aims are relevant even in philosophical studies of natural kinds, which have usually been approached from a purely metaphysical point of view. A natural kind is a grouping of objects that is not just a matter of human convention, but reflects the structure of nature. The standard project is to develop a metaphysical construal of what a natural kind is, and what distinguishes natural kinds from other kinds. However, I contend that epistemological issues are equally important, in particular the philosophical study of which particular explanatory aims scientists pursue when using kinds in their theorizing, and whether and how a grouping of objects into a kind meets the given explanatory aim (Brigandt 2009, 2011b).

  6. The philosophical importance of values in science has been particularly stressed by social studies of science and feminist philosophy of science (Douglas 2009; Kourany 2010). While some philosophers may still aim at a clear separation of epistemic and other values (where only epistemic, but not personal, socio-political, and economic values are a proper part of science and a concern for philosophy of science), at least in current biomedical research various values are so strongly intertwined in the production of knowledge that in my view a distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic values is not philosophically fruitful. A philosophy of science that endeavors to study which kinds of scientific research are socially responsible will insist on the relevance of socio-political values from the outset (Kourany 2010). While it is beyond the scope of this essay’s topic, I view values in science to be of importance for science education as well. Science ought to be taught more as a social process that is based on institutional factors and various interests. Understanding debates about global warming and evolution not only requires that scientific facts are taught, but students should learn about the motivations and societal agendas of different groups, including groups of scientists, and what standards of intellectual integrity by different parties are used and how their values are defended (Brigandt 2011a).

References

  • Beatty, J. (1984). Chance and natural selection. Philosophy of Science, 51, 183–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (1986). Integrating sciences by creating new disciplines: The case of cell biology. Biology and Philosophy, 8, 277–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2010). The downs and ups of mechanistic research: Circadian rhythm research as an exemplar. Erkenntnis, 73, 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Hamilton, A. (2007). Reduction, integration, and the unity of science: Natural, behavioral, and social sciences and the humanities. In T. A. F. Kuipers (Ed.), General philosophy of science: Focal issues (pp. 377–430). New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behe, M. J. (1996). Darwin’s black box: The biochemical challenge to evolution. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy of neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive approach. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. N., & Carson, S. (1996). The indeterministic character of evolutionary theory: No hidden variables proof but no room for determinism either. Philosophy of Science, 63, 315–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2009). Natural kinds in evolution and systematics: Metaphysical and epistemological considerations. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 77–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2010a). Beyond reduction and pluralism: Toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis, 73, 295–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2010b). The epistemic goal of a concept: Accounting for the rationality of semantic change and variation. Synthese, 177, 19–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2010c). Scientific reasoning is material inference: Combining confirmation, discovery, and explanation. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24, 31–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2011a). Critical notice of Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science by Elliott Sober, Cambridge University Press, 2008. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 41, 159–186.

  • Brigandt, I. (2011b). Natural kinds and concepts: A pragmatist and methodologically naturalistic account. In J. Knowles & H. Rydenfelt (Eds.), Pragmatism, science and naturalism (pp. 171–196). Berlin: Peter Lang Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2011c). Philosophy of biology. In S. French & J. Saatsi (Eds.), The Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Science (pp. 246–267). London: Continuum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (forthcoming). The dynamics of scientific concepts: The relevance of epistemic aims and values. In U. Feest & F. Steinle (Eds.), Scientific concepts and investigative practice. Berlin: de Gruyter.

  • Brigandt, I., & Griffiths, P. E. (2007). The importance of homology for biology and philosophy. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 633–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I., & Love, A. C. (2008). Reductionism in biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/reduction-biology.

  • Brigandt, I., & Love, A. C. (2010). Evolutionary novelty and the evo-devo synthesis: Field notes. Evolutionary Biology, 37, 93–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). The truth doesn’t explain much. In N. Cartwright (Ed.), How the laws of physics lie (pp. 44–53). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2005). Beyond reduction: Mechanisms, multifield integration and the unity of neuroscience. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 373–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2009). Mechanisms and natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 575–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2005). Relations among fields: Mendelian, cytological and molecular mechanisms. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 349–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries: Essays on mechanisms, interfield relations, and anomaly resolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Maull, N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science, 44, 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of sciences as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart, J. C., & Kirschner, M. W. (2007). The theory of facilitated variation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 104, 8582–8589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grantham, T. A. (2004). Conceptualizing the (dis)unity of science. Philosophy of Science, 71, 133–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2007). Gene. In D. L. Hull & M. Ruse (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to the philosophy of biology (pp. 85–102). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendrikse, J. L., Parssons, T. E., & Hallgrímsson, B. (2007). Evolvability as the proper focus of evolutionary developmental biology. Evolution & Development, 393–401.

  • Hull, D. L. (1974). Philosophy of biological science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, A., & Love, A. C. (in press). Aspects of reductive explanation in biological science: Intrinsicality, fundamentality, and temporality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Kellert, S. H., Longino, H. E., & Waters, C. K. (2006). Introduction: The pluralist stance. In S. H. Kellert, H. E. Longino, & C. K. Waters (Eds.), Scientific pluralism (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 19, pp. vii–xxvix). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Kirschner, M. W., & Gerhart, J. C. (2005). The plausibility of life: Resolving Darwin’s dilemma. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). 1953 and all that: A tale of two sciences. The Philosophical Review, 93, 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and causal structure. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1999). Unification as a regulative ideal. Perspectives on Science, 7, 337–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. (2010). Philosophy of science after feminism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler, M., & Wagner, G. P. (2001). How molecular is molecular developmental biology? A reply to Alex Rosenberg’s Reductionism redux: Computing the embryo. Biology and Philosophy, 16, 53–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. A. (1994). The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2005). Explaining evolutionary innovation and novelty: A historical and philosophical study of biological concepts. Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh. http://etd.library.pitt.edu/ETD/available/etd-05232005-142007.

  • Love, A. C. (2008). Explaining evolutionary innovations and novelties: Criteria of explanatory adequacy and epistemological prerequisites. Philosophy of Science, 75, 874–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2009). Typology reconfigured: From the metaphysics of essentialism to the epistemology of representation. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 51–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2010). Idealization in evolutionary developmental investigation: A tension between phenotypic plasticity and normal stages. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 365, 679–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (this issue). Interdisciplinary lessons for the teaching of biology from the practice of evo-devo. Science & Education.

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maull, N. (1977). Unifying science without reduction. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 8, 143–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R. L. (2002). Are random drift and natural selection conceptually distinct? Biology and Philosophy, 17, 33–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (2002). Integrative pluralism. Philosophy of Science, 17, 55–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (2003). Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. B., & Wagner, G. P. (2003). Innovation. In B. K. Hall & W. M. Olson (Eds.), Keywords and concepts in evolutionary developmental biology (pp. 218–227). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1949). The meaning of reduction in the natural sciences. In R. C. Stauffer (Ed.), Science and civilization (pp. 99–135). Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S. A., & Müller, G. B. (2005). Origination and innovation in the vertebrate limb skeleton: An epigenetic perspective. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Molecular and Developmental Evolution), 304B, 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2003). Complex systems, trade-offs, and theoretical population biology: Richard Levin’s “Strategy of model building in population biology” revisited. Philosophy of Science, 70, 1496–1507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2006). Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, P., & Putnam, H. (1958). Unity of science as a working hypothesis. In H. Feigl, M. Scriven & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and the mind-body problem (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 2, pp. 3–36). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Repko, A. F. (2008). Interdisciplinary research: Process and theory. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.

  • Robert, J. (2004). Embryology, epigenesis, and evolution: Taking development seriously. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (1994). Instrumental biology or the disunity of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1971). Reduction, replacement, and molecular biology. Dialectica, 25, 39–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1971). Statistical explanation and statistical relevance. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (1998). Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (1969). The Watson-Crick model and reductionism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 20, 325–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (1976). Reductionism in biology: Prospects and problems. In R. S. Cohen & A. Michalos (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1974 biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (pp. 613–632). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1980). Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 47, 350–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (2006a). Molecular epigenesis: Distributed specificity as a break in the central dogma. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 28, 527–544.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (2006b). With ‘genes’ like that, who needs an environment? Postgenomics’s argument for the ‘ontogeny of information’. Philosophy of Science, 73, 905–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vance, R. E. (1996). Heroic antireductionism and genetics: A tale of one science. Philosophy of Science, 63, S36–S45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G. P. (2000). What is the promise of developmental evolution? Part I: Why is developmental biology necessary to explain evolutionary innovations? Journal of Experimental Zoology (Molecular and Developmental Evolution), 288, 95–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M., Lewens, T., & Ariew, A. (2002). The trials of life: Natural selection and random drift. Philosophy of Science, 69, 429–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2006). Forty years of ‘The strategy’: Levins on model building and idealization. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 623–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. The Journal of Philosophy, 104, 639–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1976). Reductive explanations: A functional account. In R. S. Cohen & A. Michalos (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1974 biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (pp. 671–710). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1979). Reduction and reductionism. In P. D. Asquith & H. E. Kyburg (Eds.), Current research in philosophy of science: Proceedings of the PSA critical research problems conference (pp. 352–377). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: Piecewise approximations to reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. G. (2006). Parts and theories in compositional biology. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 471–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. G. (2011). Part-whole science. Synthese, 178, 397–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to Kostas Kampourakis, Alan Love, and an anonymous referee for comments on an earlier version of this essay. This work was funded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (Standard Research Grant 410-2008-0400).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ingo Brigandt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Brigandt, I. Explanation in Biology: Reduction, Pluralism, and Explanatory Aims. Sci & Educ 22, 69–91 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9350-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9350-7

Keywords

Navigation