Skip to main content
Log in

Risk and time preferences interaction: An experimental measurement

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We experimentally characterize and measure the interaction between risk and time preferences. Our results indicate that risk and time preferences are intertwined. We find that decision makers are insensitive to time delay for small probabilities of gains, but become progressively more sensitive to time delay as the probability of gain increases. We compare the fit of existing decision models that capture risk and time preferences. Our results indicate that the models which allow for probability-time interaction and capture magnitude effect fit the data better. We also show that accounting for risk-time preferences interaction leads to lower estimated discount rates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Prelec and Loewenstein (1991) showed that there are many parallels between the impacts of risk and time preferences on decision making.

  2. The model is based on the axiomatic system developed by Chew and Epstein (1990) that extends non-expected utility to temporal prospects.

  3. Magnitude effect implies that people are more patient when discounting larger outcomes.

  4. Andreoni and Sprenger (2012) focus on common ratio property as applied to intertemporal risk and show that different alternatives to DEU cannot explain the observed choices. In contrast, our study does not focus on a specific property but explores in more general how risk and time preferences interact with each other by estimating different decision models and comparing them.

  5. Noussair and Wu (2006), Abdellaoui et al. (2011b) focus on the time of uncertainty resolution (by fixing the time of payment), we focus on the time of payment (by fixing the time of uncertainty resolution).

  6. Similar approach has been followed by other studies (Andreoni & Sprenger, 2012; Abdellaoui et al., 2019) to avoid time of uncertainty resolution from affecting the preferences (Kreps & Porteus, 1978).

  7. We use the terms “time of payment” and “time delay” interchangeably. All models discussed in the section focus on the present value of the prospect, therefore time of payment corresponds to time delay.

  8. For prospect \(L_{2},\) this can be inferred by substituting \(w_{t}=\delta ^{t}p\) into the more general form of Eq. (1) described above.

  9. Note that, although, RSU agrees with PTT when evaluating value (or certainty equivalent) of a single outcome prospect, range effects may intervene in RSU when comparing two single outcome prospects.

  10. The sooner payment was not paid immediately but tomorrow, to ensure the transaction costs were similar for both the choices.

  11. We used colored coins as a substitute for the colored balls that were used in the experimental stimuli

  12. If the subject was chosen to receive real incentive, then one of the questions was randomly selected. For that specific question, one of the choices in the choice list was randomly selected and the uncertainty (if any) was resolved immediately by picking a coin from a box consisting of different colored coins. The subjects were paid on the specific date based on their choices and the resolved uncertainty.

  13. The results are for forty four subjects. For three subjects, the algorithm did not converge.

  14. We estimate the RSU model by assuming \(S(t)=pe^{-rt}\).

  15. The parameters of RSU are also elicited for an alternate specification of the discount rate \(r_{x}=r_{0}\left[ 1+\frac{M}{x}\right]\) in Table 14, Appendix C.

  16. We also estimated the hyperbolic discounted rank dependent utility (HDRDU) model, but the estimated AIC was higher than the DRDU model.

  17. In fact, when we consider all 44 prospects and estimate the WTU model, the K parameter is negative indicating the dependence of utility on time of payment.

References

  • Abdellaoui, M., Baillon, A., Placido, L., & Wakker, P. P. (2011a). The rich domain of uncertainty: Source functions and their experimental implementation. American Economic Review, 101, 695–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., Diecidue, E., & Öncüler, A. (2011b). Risk preferences at different time periods: An experimental investigation. Management Science, 57, 975–987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., Kemel, E., Panin, A., & Vieider, F. M. (2019). Measuring time and risk preferences in an integrated framework. Games and Economic Behavior, 115, 459–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., L’Haridon, O., & Paraschiv, C. (2011c). Experienced vs. described uncertainty: Do we need two prospect theory specifications? Management Science, 57, 1879–1895.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akaike, H. (1998). Information theory and an extension of the maximum likelihood principle. In Selected papers of hirotugu akaike (pp. 199–213). Springer.

  • Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l’école américaine. Econometrica, 21, 503–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderhub, V., Güth, W., Gneezy, U., & Sonsino, D. (2001). On the interaction of risk and time preferences: An experimental study. German Economic Review, 2, 239–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, S., Harrison, G. W., Lau, M. I., & Rutström, E. E. (2008). Eliciting risk and time preferences. Econometrica, 76, 583–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J., & Sprenger, C. (2012). Risk preferences are not time preferences. American Economic Review, 102, 3357–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Attema, A. E., Bleichrodt, H., Rohde, K. I., & Wakker, P. P. (2010). Time-tradeoff sequences for analyzing discounting and time inconsistency. Management Science, 56, 2015–2030.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baucells, M., & Cillo, A. (2019). The intuitive present value of cash flows. Working Paper.

  • Baucells, M., & Heukamp, F. H. (2010). Common ratio using delay. Theory and Decision, 68, 149–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baucells, M., & Heukamp, F. H. (2012). Probability and time trade-off. Management Science, 58, 831–842.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baucells, M., Kontek, K., & Lewandowski, M. (2018). Range and sign dependent utility for risk and time. Working Paper.

  • Chapman, G. B., & Elstein, A. S. (1995). Valuing the future: Temporal discounting of health and money. Medical Decision Making, 15, 373–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheung, S. L. (2015). Risk preferences are not time preferences: On the elicitation of time preference under conditions of risk: comment. American Economic Review, 105, 2242–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S. H., & Epstein, L. G. (1990). Nonexpected utility preferences in a temporal framework with an application to consumption-savings behaviour. Journal of Economic Theory, 50, 54–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epper, T., Fehr-Duda, H., & Bruhin, A. (2011). Viewing the future through a warped lens: Why uncertainty generates hyperbolic discounting. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 43, 169–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Rubinstein, A. (1982). Time preference. International Economic Review, 23, 677–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, C. R., & Tversky, A. (1995). Ambiguity aversion and comparative ignorance. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 110, 585–603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerber, A., & Rohde, K. I. (2018). Weighted temporal utility. Economic Theory, 66, 187–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halevy, Y. (2008). Strotz meets allais: Diminishing impatience and the certainty effect. American Economic Review, 98, 1145–1162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halevy, Y. (2015). Time consistency: Stationarity and time invariance. Econometrica, 83, 335–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ida, T., & Goto, R. (2009). Simultaneous measurement of time and risk preferences: Stated preference discrete choice modeling analysis depending on smoking behavior. International Economic Review, 50, 1169–1182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keren, G., & Roelofsma, P. (1995). Immediacy and certainty in intertemporal choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 63, 287–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirby, K. N., & Santiesteban, M. (2003). Concave utility, transaction costs, and risk in measuring discounting of delayed rewards. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 29, 66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kontek, K., & Lewandowski, M. (2017). Range-dependent utility. Management Science, 64, 2812–2832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kothiyal, A., Spinu, V., & Wakker, P. P. (2014). An experimental test of prospect theory for predicting choice under ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 48, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D. M., & Porteus, E. L. (1978). Temporal resolution of uncertainty and dynamic choice theory. Econometrica, (pp. 185–200).

  • Laibson, D. (1997). Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112, 443–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (1992). Anomalies in intertemporal choice: Evidence and an interpretation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107, 573–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Thaler, R. H. (1989). Anomalies: Intertemporal choice. Journal of Economic perspectives, 3, 181–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miao, B., & Zhong, S. (2015). Risk preferences are not time preferences: Separating risk and time preference: Comment. American Economic Review, 105, 2272–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noussair, C., & Wu, P. (2006). Risk tolerance in the present and the future: An experimental study. Managerial and Decision Economics, 27, 401–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prelec, D. (1998). The probability weighting function. Econometrica, 66, 497–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prelec, D., & Loewenstein, G. (1991). Decision making over time and under uncertainty: A common approach. Management Science, 37, 770–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 3, 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Read, D. (2001). Is time-discounting hyperbolic or subadditive? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 23, 5–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. (2010). Prospect Theory for Risk and Ambiguity. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P. (2008). Explaining the characteristics of the power CRRA utility family. Health Economics, 17, 1329–1344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P., & Deneffe, D. (1996). Eliciting von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities when probabilities are distorted or unknown. Management Science, 42, 1131–1150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, B. J., & Chapman, G. B. (2005). The combined effects of risk and time on choice: Does uncertainty eliminate the immediacy effect? does delay eliminate the certainty effect? Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 96, 104–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Manel Baucells, Enrico Diecidue, Matthias Seifert, Konstantinos Stouras for their helpful comments on this draft of the paper. We also thank Mohammed Abdellaoui, Ehud Lehrer, and Bob Nau for their helpful comments during the different stages of the project. We acknowledge the help rendered by INSEAD Sorbonne lab research assistants Hoai Huong Ngo and Jean-Yves Mariette with the data collection. We also gratefully acknowledge support from the People Programme (Marie Curie Actions) of the European Union’s Seventh Framework Programme FP7/2007-2013/ under REA grant agreement 290255 and HEC Paris.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeeva Somasundaram.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary file1 (PDF 3.32 MB)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Somasundaram, J., Eli, V. Risk and time preferences interaction: An experimental measurement. J Risk Uncertain 65, 215–238 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09394-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09394-9

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation