Skip to main content
Log in

Learning in the Allais paradox

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Whereas both the Allais paradox, the first empirical challenge of the classical rationality assumptions, and learning have been the focus of many experimental investigations, no experimental study exists today into learning in the pure context of the Allais paradox. This paper presents such a study. We find that choices converge to expected utility maximization if subjects are given the opportunity to learn by both thought and experience, but less so when they learn by thought only. To the extent that genuine preferences should be measured with proper learning and incentives, our study gives the first pure demonstration that irrationalities such as in the Allais paradox are less pronounced than often thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Allais, Maurice. (1953). “Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de l’Ecole Américaine,” Econometrica 21, 503–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barron, Greg and Ido Erev. (2003). “Small Feedback-Based Decisions and Their Limited Correspondence to Description-Based Decisions,” Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 16, 215–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, Kenneth G. (1999). “Why Experiments in Economics?” Economic Journal 109, F16–F24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bone, John, John Hey and John Suckling. (1999). “Are Groups More (or Less) Consistent than Individuals?” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 18, 63–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brookshire, David S. and Don L. Coursey. (1987). “Measuring the Value of a Public Good: An Empirical Comparison of Elicitation Procedures,” American Economic Review 77, 554–566.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin F. (1995). “Individual Decision Making.” In John H. Kagel and Alvin E. Roth (eds), Handbook of Experimental Economics 587–703. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Camerer, Colin F. (2003). Behavioral Game Theory: Experiments in Strategic Interaction (Roundtable Series in Behaviorial Economics). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Camerer, Colin F. and Teck-Hua Ho. (1999). “Experience-Weighted Attraction Learning in Normal Form Games,” Econometrica 67, 827–874.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbone, Enrica and John D. Hey. (2000). “Which Error Story Is Best?” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 20, 161−176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conlisk, John. (1989). “Three Variants on the Allais Example,” American Economic Review 79, 392–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, James C. and David M. Grether. (1996). “The Preference Reversal Phenomenon: Response Mode, Markets and Incentives,” Economic Theory 7, 381–405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cubitt, Robin P., Chris Starmer and Robert Sugden. (1998). “On the Validity of the Random Lottery Incentive System,” Experimental Economics 1, 115–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cubitt, Robin P., Chris Starmer and Robert Sugden. (2001). “Discovered Preferences and the Experimental Evidence of Violations of Expected Utility Theory,” Journal of Economic Methodology 8, 385–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einav, Liran. (2005). “Informational Asymmetries and Observational Learning in Search,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 30, 241−259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erev, Ido and Alvin E. Roth. (1998). “Predicting how People Play Games: Reinforcement Learning in Experimental Games with Unique, Mixed Strategy Equilibria,” American Economic Review 88, 848–881.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Dorla A. (1997). “The Role of Markets in Reducing Expected Utility Violations,” Journal of Political Economy 105, 622–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harless, David W. (1992). “Actions versus Prospects: The Effect of Problem Representation on Regret,” American Economic Review 82, 634–649.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harless, David W. and Colin F. Camerer. (1994). “The Predictive Utility of Generalized Expected Utility Theories,” Econometrica 62, 1251–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, Ralf and Andreas Ortmann. (2001). “Experimental Practices In Economics: A Challenge for Psychologists?” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24, 383–403.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt, Charles A. (1986). “Preference Reversals and the Independence Axiom,” American Economic Review 76, 508–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, Stephen J. (2006). “Does Learning Diminish Violations of Independence, Coalescing and Monotonicity?” Theory and Decision 61, 93–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky. (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk,” Econometrica 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keren, Gideon B. and Willem A. Wagenaar. (1987). “Violation of Utility Theory in Unique and Repeated Gambles,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 13, 29–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, John A. (2004). “Neoclassical Theory versus Prospect Theory: Evidence from the Marketplace,” Econometrica 72, 615–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham. (1988). “Further Evidence of the Impact of Regret and Disappointment in Choice under Uncertainty,” Economica 55, 47–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, Peter G. Moffat and Robert Sugden. (2002). “A Microeconometric Test of Alternative Stochastic Theories of Risky Choice,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 24, 103–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, Chris Starmer and Robert Sugden. (2003). “Do Anomalies Disappear in Repeated Markets?” The Economic Journal 113, C153–C166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham and Robert Sugden. (1982). “Regret Theory: An Alternative Theory of Rational Choice under Uncertainty,” Economic Journal 92, 805–824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacCrimmon, Kenneth R. (1968). “Descriptive and Normative Implications of the Decision-Theory Postulates.” In Karl H. Borch and Jan Mossin (eds), Risk and Uncertainty 3–23, St. Martin’s Press, New York.

  • Myagkov, Mikhail G. and Charles R. Plott. (1997). “Exchange Economies and Loss Exposure: Experiments Exploring Prospect Theory and Competitive Equilibria in Market Environments,” American Economic Review 87, 801–828.

  • Offerman, Theo, Jan Potters and Joep Sonnemans. (2002). “Imitation and Belief Learning in an Oligopoly Experiment,” Review of Economic Studies 69, 973–997.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, John. (1981). “Risk Perception and Risk Aversion among Australian Farmers,” Australian Journal of Agricultural Economics 25, 160–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, Ulrich and Tibor Neugebauer. (2006). “Testing Expected Utility in the Presence of Errors”. Economic Journal, forthcoming.

  • Slovic, Paul and Amos Tversky. (1974). “Who Accepts Savage’s Axiom?” Behavioral Science 19, 368–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Vernon L. (1982). “Microeconomic Systems as an Experimental Science,” American Economic Review 72, 923–955.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris. (2000). “Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory: The Hunt for a Descriptive Theory of Choice under Risk,” Journal of Economic Literature 38, 332–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris and Robert Sugden. (1989). “Probability and Juxtaposition Effects: An Experimental Investigation of the Common Ratio Effect,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 2, 159–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris and Robert Sugden. (1991). “Does the Random-Lottery Incentive System Elicit True Preferences? An Experimental Investigation,” American Economic Review 81, 971–978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman. (1986). “Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions,” Journal of Business 59, S251–S278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman. (1992). “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter P. Wakker.

Additional information

Paul Anand and Stefan Trautmann made helpful comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kuilen, G.v.d., Wakker, P.P. Learning in the Allais paradox. J Risk Uncertainty 33, 155–164 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-006-0390-3

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-006-0390-3

Keywords

Navigation