Skip to main content
Log in

Epistocracy and Public Interests

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Epistocratic systems of government have received renewed attention, and considerable opposition, in recent political philosophy. Although they vary significantly in form, epistocracies generally reject universal suffrage. But can they maintain the advantages of universal suffrage despite rejecting it? This paper develops an argument for a significant instrumental advantage of universal suffrage: that governments must take into account the interests of all of those enfranchised in their policy decisions or else risk losing power. This is called ‘the Interests Argument’. One problem for the Interests Argument is that governments are not entirely responsive to voter interests, partly because voters do not always know what is in their interests. I will show how this epistemic claim can be used to support certain forms of epistocracy, but deny that it undermines the Interests Argument. I then consider whether we can identify forms of epistocracy that preserve the benefits of the Interests Argument whilst overcoming the epistemic limitations of democracy. I propose six forms of epistocracy, and argue that two are able to maintain these benefits, hence providing an evaluation of the relative strengths of these epistocracies with respect to one of the most valuable instrumental benefits of universal suffrage. Whilst epistocracy lacks many of the advantages of democracy, this paper shows that some forms fare better than others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that whilst Estlund coined the term ‘epistocracy’ he does not support it. Other recent theories that diverge from universal suffrage include defences of rule by sortition (Guerrero 2014).

  2. See Arlen and Rossi (forthcoming), Gunn (2019), Klocksiem (2019), Moraro (2018), Reiss (2019), Talisse (forthcoming) and Somin (forthcoming). For some responses, see Brennan (forthcoming).

  3. Whilst this typology overlaps in places, these positions are distinct from one another. For instance, those electing the lifelong ruler in (b) could be restricted in the sense of (c) or (d), and hence (b) would be compatible with (c) and (d). However, both (c) and (d) are proposed to operate in contexts of regular election cycles, which would then be incompatible with (b). And whilst Guardians in (a) could put in place a system that decides who rules based on how knowledgeable voters would vote, as in (f), this cannot be the case for Plato’s Guardianship which has no elections at all. The distinctions between the different epistocratic systems will become clearer in the later sections.

  4. The US government estimates that China’s PRC has detained more than one million members of religious groups in internment camps ‘and subjected them to forced disappearance, political indoctrination, torture, psychological and physical abuse, including forced sterilization and sexual abuse, forced labor, and prolonged detention without trial because of their religion and ethnicity’. See 2019 Report on International Religious Freedom: China—Xinjiang: https://www.state.gov/reports/2019-report-on-international-religious-freedom/china/xinjiang/.

  5. And depending on the country, those in prison and citizens with mental impairments as well. For arguments that minors and the cognitively impaired should be enfranchised, see López-Guerra (2012).

  6. See the report from 2006 by Human Rights Watch, Building Towers, Cheating Workers: Exploitation of Migrant Construction Workers in the United Arab Emirates. According to the report, ‘the federal government of the UAE…has failed to enforce UAE law that since 1980 has required the government to implement a minimum wage…[T]he migrant [construction] worker…on average receives the equivalent of US$175 a month for his labor on a construction site. This stands in stark contrast to the average per capita income in the UAE of $2106 a month’ (p. 6).

  7. For other seminal works on this theory, see Fiorina (1981) and Kramer (1971), and for recent critical appraisal, Achen and Bartels (2016) and Healy and Malhotra (2013).

  8. Karl Popper referred to Plato’s system as ‘the ruler of learnedness,’ or, ‘sophocracy’ (1945, p. 144).

  9. Arguably, the interests of the members of each unit are better represented under such a consensual system than they are under party systems where the interests of a minority group can be ignored.

  10. See Brennan (2016) for extensive discussion of this issue.

References

  • Achen, Christopher, and Larry Bartels. 2016. Democracy for Realists: Why Elections Do not Produce Responsive Government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Althaus, Scott. 1998. Information Effects in Collective Preferences. American Political Science Review 92(3): 545–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arlen, Gordon, and Enzo Rossi. Forthcoming. Is This What Democracy Looks Like? (Never Mind Epistocracy). Inquiry.

  • Bechtel, Michael, and Jen Hainmueller. 2011. How Lasting is Voter Gratitude? An Analysis of the Short- and Long-Term Electoral Returns to Beneficial Policy. American Journal of Political Science 55(4): 852–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Jason. 2011. The Right to a Competent Electorate. The Philosophical Quarterly 61(245): 700–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Jason. 2016. Against Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Jason. 2018. Does the Demographic Objection to Epistocracy Succeed? Res Publica 24: 53–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Jason. Forthcoming. Giving Epistocracy a Fair Hearing. Inquiry.

  • Estlund, David. 2003. Why not Epistocracy? In Desire, Identity, and Existence: Essays in Honor of T. M. Penner, ed. N. Reshotko, 53–69. Kelowna: Academic Printing & Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T., S. Gailmard, and A. Sandroni. 2009. Moral Bias in Large Elections: Theory and Experimental Evidence. American Political Science Review 103(2): 175–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferejohn, J. 1986. Incumbent Performance and Electoral Control. Public Choice 50(1–3): 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiorina, M. P. 1981. Retrospective Voting in American National Elections. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, Alexander. 2014. Against Elections: The Lottocratic Alternative. Philosophy and Public Affairs 42(2): 136–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gunn, Paul. 2019. Against Epistocracy. Critical Review 31(1): 26–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harper, Ida Husted. 2005. The Life and Work of Susan B. Anthony, Volume 1. Indianapolis and Kansas City: The Bowen-Merrill Company, originally published 1899.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healy, Andrew, and Neil Malhotra. 2013. Retrospective Voting Reconsidered. Annual Review of Political Science 16: 285–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, G. H. 1971. Short-Term Fluctuations in U.S. Voting Behaviour. American Political Science Review 71: 131–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klocksiem, Justin. 2019. Epistocracy is a Wolf in Wolf’s Clothing. The Journal of Ethics 23: 19–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • López-Guerra, Claudio. 2012. Enfranchising Minors and the Mentally Impaired. Social Theory and Practice 38(1): 115–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • López-Guerra, Claudio. 2014. Democracy and Disenfranchisement: The Morality of Electoral Exclusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1991. Considerations on Representative Government. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, originally published 1861.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moraro, Piero. 2018. Against Epistocracy. Social Theory and Practice 44(2): 199–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, Thomas. 2018. Plural Voting for the Twenty-First Century. The Philosophical Quarterly 68: 286–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, Julian. 2019. Expertise, Agreement, and the Nature of Social Scientific Facts or: Against Epistocracy. Social Epistemology 33(2): 183–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl. 1945. The Open Society and Its Enemies (2 Volumes). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Graham, and Maija Setälä. 2018. Mini-Publics and Deliberative Democracy. In The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy, ed. Andre Bächtiger, John S. Dryzek, Jane Mansbridge, and Mark Warren, 300–314. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Somin, Ilya. Forthcoming. The Promise and Peril of Epistocracy. Inquiry.

  • Talisse, Robert B. Forthcoming. The Trouble with Hooligans. Inquiry.

  • Wiredu, Kwasi. 1995. Democracy and Consensus in African Traditional Politics: A Plea for a Non-Party Polity. The Centennial Review 39(1): 53–64.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Finlay Malcolm.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Malcolm, F. Epistocracy and Public Interests. Res Publica 28, 173–192 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-021-09502-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-021-09502-7

Keywords

Navigation