Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Bargaining within the family can generate a political gender gap

  • Published:
Review of Economics of the Household Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Consider spouses who engage in Nash bargaining to allocate resources between them. The person with a higher income when unmarried enjoys a larger share of the joint income, and benefits less from an increase in joint income. This difference can cause spouses who have the same utility functions and the same family incomes to differ in their benefits from governmental tax and spending policies, and to cast opposing votes. In particular, these incentives can generate a gender gap, with women more supportive than men of governmental taxes and spending.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Results from the American Community Survey 20082011 show that the husband earns more than the wife in 73 % of the couples. See Bertrand et al. (2015).

  2. When the intertemporal discount factor is 1, the same solution arises with Nash bargaining as in the Rubinstein bargaining game. Some of the results described below can appear under less selfish behavior. Consider warm glow (Andreoni 1990), where a spouse gets utility from giving to the other, and suppose the husband’s income or wealth exceeds the wife’s, so that any intra-family transfers are made from him to her. A husband who gets a warm glow from giving to his wife would oppose a tax policy that taxes men in his situation, using the revenue to give governmental benefits to women, including his wife. For such an arrangement, though it affects consumption the same way as a voluntary transfer, generates no warm glow. Indeed, he might oppose the policy even if the benefits given his wife are greater than the tax he pays—he wants to be the provider.

  3. thehill.com/blogs/blog-briefing-room/news/267101-gallup-2012-election-had-the-largest-gender-gap-in-history. Accessed 12/18/2012

  4. The differences, however, declined as election day approached. Other studies also find that women favor redistributive policies more than men do. See Kornhauser (1987), Shapiro and Mahajan (1986), and Welch and Hibbing (1992).

  5. http://www.cawp.rutgers.edu/fast_facts/voters/documents/ggapissues, retrieved February 9, 2012.

  6. An alternative approach is pure non-cooperative behavior, as discussed by Lundberg and Pollak (1994), and Konrad and Lommerud (1995).

  7. Table 16, “Labor force characteristics by race and ethnicity, 2012”, U.S. Bureau of Labor Statistics, October 2013.

  8. The function U exhibits non-decreasing relative risk aversion if \(-yU''(y){/}U'(y)\) is non-decreasing in y. The following discussion restricts utility functions to satisfy this criterion. Note that for \(U(y)=ln(y),\) relative risk aversion is constant (and thus non-decreasing), and that for \(U(y)=y^{\delta }\) (with \(\delta > 0\)), relative risk aversion is also constant.

  9. Evidence relating to the concern about relative incomes is given by Frank (1985).

  10. The result is clearest for linear utility. Here, each spouse receives his or her income when unmarried plus half the marriage surplus. Suppose initially that the after-tax income of an umarried man is 3/4 and that the after-tax income of an unmarried woman is 1/4. Suppose family income is 1.5. The surplus from marriage is then 1 / 2, and so the wife’s consumption is \(1{/}4+(1{/}2)(1{/}2)=1{/}2\). Now suppose tax policy reduces the income of an unmarried man to 2 / 3, increases the income of an unmarried woman to 1 / 3, and reduces family income to slightly over 4 / 3, say to \(4{/}3+\Delta.\) The surplus from marriage is \(1{/}3+\Delta.\) The married woman’s income thus increases from 1/2 to \(1{/}3+(1{/}3+\Delta )(1{/}2)=1{/}2+\Delta.\)

  11. http://www.gallup.com/poll/120839/women?likely?democrats?regardless?age.aspx

  12. Commitment can occur early in marriage, e.g. by the choice of buying a house with a large kitchen or instead a large media room and man cave. The choice of where to live—near the husband’s job or near the wife’s job—can also affect future consumption allocations.

  13. The opposite result can occur if G is sufficiently large to make the marginal utility of the woman’s income when single, and when she receives G, decline from a value much larger than the man’s to a value that is close to his. That change would reduce her share of the surplus from marriage.

Abbreviations

U :

Utility function

\(Y_M\) :

Income of an unmarried man

\(1-Y_M\) :

Income of an unmarried woman

\(Y_H\) :

Family income

\(s_h\) :

1 − tax rate on income of unmarried man

\(s_w\) :

1 − tax rate on income of unmarried woman

x :

Share of family income allocated to husband

References

  • Alvarez, R. M., & McCaffery, E. J. (2000). Gender and tax. In S. Tolleson-Rinehart & J. J. Josephson (Eds.), Gender and American politics: Women, men and the political process. New York: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, R. M, & McCaffery, E. J. (2001). Is there a gender gap in fiscal political preferences? Working Paper, California Institute of Technology.

  • Andreoni, J. (1990). Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm glow giving. Economic Journal, 100, 464–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertrand, M., Kamenica, E., & Pan, J. (2015). Gender identity and relative income within households. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 130, 571–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Box-Steffensmeier, J. M., De Beoff, S., & Lin, T. (2004). The dynamics of the partisan gender gap. American Political Science Review, 98, 515–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browning, E. K. (1975). Why the social insurance budget is too large in a democracy. Economic Inquiry, 13, 373–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chaney, C. K., Alvarez, R. M., & Nagler, J. (1998). Explaining the gender gap in US presidential elections, 1980–1992. Political Research Quarterly, 51, 311–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connelly, M. (2000). Who voted: A portrait of American politics, 1976–2000. New York Times, Vol. 4, p. 11, November 12, 2000.

  • Conover, P. J. (1988). Feminists and the gender gap. Journal of Politics, 50, 985–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conway, M. M. (2008). The gender gap: A comparison across racial and ethnic groups. In L. D. Whitaker (Ed.), Voting the gender gap. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deitch, C. (1988). Sex differences in support for government spending. In C. Mueller (Ed.), The politics of the gender gap: The social construction of political influence (pp. 192–216). Newbury Park: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edlund, L., & Pande, R. (2002). Why have women become left-wing? The political gender gap and the decline in marriage. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117, 917–961.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erie, S. P., & Rein, M. (1988). Women and the welfare state. In C. M. Mueller (Ed.), The politics of the gender gap: The social construction of political influence (pp. 173–191). Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. H. (1985). Choosing the right pond: Human behavior and the quest for status. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossbard, S. (2015). The marriage motive: A price theory of marriage. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gugl, E. (2009). Income splitting, specialization, and intra-family distribution. Canadian Journal of Economics, 42(3), 1050–1071.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iyigun, M., & Walsh, R. P. (2007). Endogenous gender power, household labor supply and the demographic transition. Journal of Development Economics, 82, 138–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iversen, T., & Rosenbluth, R. (2006). The political economy of gender: Explaining cross-national variation in the gender division of labor and the gender voting gap. American Journal of Political Science, 50, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemnitz, A., & Thum, M. (2015). Gender power, fertility, and family policy. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 117, 220–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K. A., & Lommerud, K. E. (1995). Family policy with non-cooperative families. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 97, 581–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K. A., & Lommerud, K. E. (2000). The bargaining family revisited. Canadian Journal of Economics, 33, 471–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornhauser, M. E. (1987). The rhetoric of the anti-progressive income tax movement: A typical male reaction. Michigan Law Review, 86, 465–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leroux, M., Pestieau, P., & Racionero, M. (2011). Voting on pensions: Sex and marriage. European Journal of Political Economy, 27, 281–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lundberg, S., & Pollak, R. A. (1993). Separate spheres bargaining and the marriage market. Journal of Political Economy, 100, 988–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lundberg, S., & Pollak, R. A. (1994). Noncooperative bargaining models of marriage. American Economic Review, 84, 132–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manser, M., & Brown, M. (1980). Marriage and household decision-making: A bargaining analysis. International Economic Review, 21, 31–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manza, J., & Brooks, C. (1998). The gender gap in U.S. presidential elections: When? Why? Implications? American Journal of Sociology, 103, 1235–1266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mattei, L. W., & Mattei, F. (1998). If men stayed home.. The gender gap in recent congressional elections. Political Research Quarterly, 51, 411–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCaffery, E. J. (1997). Taxing women. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McElroy, M. B., & Horney, M. J. (1981). Nash-bargained household decisions: Towards a generalization of the theory of demand. International Economic Review, 22, 333–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pechman, J. A., & Engelhardt, G. V. (1990). The income tax treatment of the family: An international perspective. National Tax Journal, 43, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, H. S. (1987). The marriage tax is down but not out. National Tax Journal, 40, 567–575.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlozman, K. L., Burns, N., Verba, S., & Donahue, J. (1995). Gender and citizen participation: Is there a different voice? American Journal of Political Science, 39, 267–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, R., & Mahajan, H. (1986). Gender differences in policy preferences: A summary of trends from the 1960s to the 1980s. Public Opinion Quarterly, 50, 42–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, W., Parker, K., & Taylor P. (2013). Married mothers who out-earn their husbands. In Breadwinner Moms, Chap. 3. Pew Research Center. http://www.pewsocialtrends.org/files/2013/05/Breadwinner_moms_final.pdf. Accessed 1 Dec 2015.

  • Welch, S., & Hibbing, J. (1992). Financial conditions, gender, and voting in American national elections. Journal of Politics, 54, 197–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wrede, M. (2000). Income splitting—Is it good for both partners in the marriage? CESifo Working Paper No. 391.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amihai Glazer.

Additional information

We are grateful to the editor and to the referees for comments which helped us improve the paper.

Appendix

Appendix

Proposition 1

In the allocation under Nash bargaining, the husband’s consumption is 1 / 2 if and only if \(s_hY_M =s_w(1-Y_M );\) that is, if and only if the income of an unmarried man equals the income of an unmarried woman.

Proof

  1. (i)

    Let \(x=1{/}2.\) Then the left-hand side of (2) equals 1, and \(U(xY_H )=U((1-x)Y_H ).\) Hence \(U(s_hY_M )=U(s_w(1-Y_M ))\) and \(s_hY_M =s_w(1-Y_M ).\)

  2. (ii)

    Let \(s_hY_M =s_w(1-Y_M ).\) Clearly, Eq. (2) holds for \(x=1{/}2.\) Now suppose \(x>1{/}2.\) (An equivalent argument holds for \(x<1{/}2\).) Then \(xY_H>(1-x)Y_H\). The assumptions that \(U'>0\) and \(U''<0\) imply that \(U(xY_H )>U((1-x)Y_H )\) and that \(U\ '(xY_H )<U''((1-x)Y_H )\). Thus, the left-hand side of (2) is less than 1 whereas the right-hand side of (2) exceeds 1, leading to a contradiction. Hence \(x=1{/}2\).

\(\square\)

Proposition 2

At any Nash bargaining allocation, \(dx{/}dY_M >0\). That is, the husband’s share of consumption within the family increases when his unmarried income increases relative to that of his wife when unmarried.

Proof

The second-order condition for a maximum of (1) requires that

$$\begin{aligned} D= & {} \frac{U''(Y_H x)}{U'((1-x)Y_H )}+\frac{ U'(Y_H x)}{U((1-x)Y_H )-U((1-Y_M )s_w} \\&-\frac{U''((1-Y_H )x)U'(Y_H x)}{\left( U'((1-x)Y_H )\right) ^{2}}-\frac{U'((1-Y_H )x)\left( U(Y_H x)-U(Y_M s_h)\right) }{\left( U((1-x)Y_H )-U((1-Y_M )s_w\right) ^{2}} \\< & {} \,0. \end{aligned}$$
(3)

Differentiating (2) gives

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{dx}{dY_M }=-\frac{1}{D}U'(xY_H )U'(s_w(1-Y_M ))s_w+U'((1-x)Y_H )U'(s_hY_M)s_h, \end{aligned}$$

which is positive. \(\square\)

Proposition 3

Let the tax rates be zero, or \(s_h=s_w=1\). and suppose family income \(Y_H\) equals 1. Then the husband’s share of family consumption is \(x=Y_M\), or his income when unmarried.

Proof

Let M be the maximand for the Nash bargaining solution. Under the assumptions of the Proposition,

$$\begin{aligned} M=(U(x)-U(Y_M ))(U(1-x)-U(1-Y_M )) \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial M}{\partial x}=(U(1-x)-U(1-Y_M ))U'(x)+(U(x)-U(Y_M ))U'(1-x)(-1). \end{aligned}$$

The value of \(\partial M{/}\partial x\) is 0 at \(x=Y_M\). Hence establishing Proposition(3) requires showing that \(\partial ^{2}M{/}\partial x^{2}<0\) at \(x=Y_M\).

We have

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial ^{2}M}{\partial x^{2}}=U''(x)(U(1-x)-U(1-Y_M ))+U''(1-x)(U(x)-U(Y_M))-2U'(x)U'(1-x). \end{aligned}$$

At \(x=Y_M\) this expression becomes \(-2U'(x)U'(1-x)\), which is negative. Thus, \(x=Y_M\) is the Nash bargaining solution for \(Y_H =1\). \(\square\)

Proposition 4

An increase in the tax rate on an unmarried man (holding constant both family income and the after-tax income of the unmarried woman) reduces the husband’s share of consumption within the family.

Implicitly differentiating (2) gives

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{dx}{d(1-s_h)} = D\frac{U'(s_hY_M )}{U((1-x)Y_H )-U(s_w(1-Y_M ))}, \end{aligned}$$

where D is defined in (3). Because marginal utility is positive, \(U'(s_hY_M )>0\). And because the woman will obtain at least as high utility when married as when unmarried, \((U((1-x)Y_H )-U(s_w(1-Y_M ))>0\). Therefore \(dx{/}d(1-s_h)<0\).

Proposition 5

Let \(Y_M >1{/}2\), and let \(Y_H >1\). Then the allocation under Nash bargaining is \(1{/}2<x<Y_M\). That is, the husband’s consumption when married is less than his share of the joint income of the man and woman when unmarried.

Proof

Suppose \(Y_M > 1{/}2\). Without loss of generality, let \(s_w=s_h=1\). Let \(M=(U(Y_H (Y_M -\epsilon ))-U(Y_M ))(U(Y_H (1-(Y_M -\epsilon )))-U(1-Y_M ))\). This expression is the maximand for the Nash bargaining solution, which is maximized at \(x=Y_M -\epsilon <Y_M\) if and only if \(dM{/}d\epsilon >0\) at \(\epsilon =0\).

Evaluating at \(\varepsilon =0\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{dM}{d\varepsilon }= & {} \left[ U(Y_H (1-Y_M )-U(1-Y_M )\right] U'(Y_H Y_M )(-Y_H ) \\&+\left[ U(Y_H Y_M )-U(Y_M )\right] U'(Y_H (1-Y_M ))Y_H. \end{aligned}$$
(4)

Therefore, \(dM{/}d\epsilon >0\) if and only if \([U(Y_H Y_M )-U(Y_M )]U'(Y_H (1-Y_M ))>[U(Y_H (1-Y_M ))-U(1-Y_M )]U'Y_H Y_M )\), or if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{U'(Y_H (1-Y_M ))}{U'(Y_H Y_M )}>\frac{ U(Y_H (1-Y_M ))-U(1-Y_M )}{U(Y_H Y_M )-U(Y_M )}. \end{aligned}$$
(5)

By the Generalized Mean Value Theorem, (5) is equivalent to:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{U'(Y_H (1-Y_M ))}{U'(Y_H Y_M )}>\frac{ 1-Y_M }{Y_M }\frac{U'(\zeta (1-Y_M ))}{U'\left( \zeta Y_M \right) } \end{aligned}$$
(6)

for some \(\zeta\) such that \(1<\zeta <Y_H\).

By assumption, \(Y_M > 1 - Y_M\), thus, a sufficient condition for (6) to hold is that \(d[U'(Y_H \ (1-Y_M )){/}U'(Y_H Y_M )]{/}dY_H >= 0\). The derivative is then

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{d\left( U'(Y_H (1-Y_M )){/}U'(Y_H Y_M )\right) }{dY_H }\\&\quad =\frac{U'((1-Y_M )Y_H )}{U'(Y_M Y_H )}\left[ \frac{(1-Y_M )U''((1-Y_M )Y_H ))}{ U'((1-Y_M )Y_H )}-\frac{Y_M U''(Y_M Y_H ))}{U'(Y_M Y_H )}\right] . \end{aligned}$$

The second term in the above equation is zero for constant relative risk aversion, and is positive for increasing relative risk aversion. Thus, at \(\epsilon = 0\), \(dM{/}d\epsilon > 0\). Hence \(1{/}2<x<Y_M\) when \(Y_M >1{/}2\). \(\square\)

Proposition 6

Let \(x>1{/}2\), let \(Y_H \ge 1\). Then \(dx{/}dY_H <0\). That is, an increase in a family’s income reduces the husband’s share of family consumption.

Proof

Use the definition of D from (3) and differentiate (2) to obtain

$$\begin{aligned} dx^{*}D= & {} -dY_H \\&\times \,(xU''(xY_H )[U((1-x)Y_H )-U(s_w(1-Y_M ))] \\&+(1-x)U'(xY_H )U'((1-x)Y_H ) \\&-(1-x)U''((1-x)Y_H )[U(xY_H )-U(s_hY_M )] \\&-xU'(xY_H )U'((1-x)Y_H )). \end{aligned}$$
(7)

Rearrange and substitute from Eq. (2) to obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{dx}{dY_H }= & {} -\frac{1}{D} ((1-2x)U'(xY_H )U'((-x)Y_H ) \\&+[U((1-x)Y_H )-U(s_w(1-Y_M ))] \\&U'(xY_H )\left[ \frac{xU''(xY_H )}{U'(xY_H )}\right] -(1-x)\frac{U''(1-x)Y_H }{U'(1-x)Y_H }) \\\le & {} -\frac{1}{D}(1-2x)U'(xY_H )U'((1-x)Y_H ), \end{aligned}$$
(8)

which is negative for \(x>1{/}2\). \(\square\)

Proposition 7

Let the equilibrium have the husband enjoy more than half of the family’s consumption (or \(x>1{/}2\) ). Then in a Nash bargaining solution, an increase in a family’s income, \(Y_H\), increases each spouse’s consumption.

Proof

First, by Proposition 6, an increase in \(Y_H\) increases the wife’s share of family consumption \((1-x)\) and thus her utility when married must increase. Suppose \(dx{/}dY_H <0\), so that the husband’s share of consumption falls with an increase in \(Y_H\). Let \(Y_H ^{*}\) be slightly larger than \(Y_H\). Let \(x^{*}\) be the allocation under the Nash bargaining solution associated with \(Y_H ^{*}\). Let \(Y_H ^{*}x^{*}<Y_H x\). Then \(U'(Y_H ^{*}x^{*})\ge U'(Y_H x)\) and \(U'(1-x^{*})Y_H ^{*}<U'((1-x)Y_H )\), because the wife’s consumption unequivocally increases.

Hence, the left-hand side of (2) increases. But because \(U(x{*}Y_H ^{*})-U(s_h(1-Y_M ))\le U(xY_H )-U(s_hY_M )\) and \(U((1-x)Y_H ^{*})-U(s_w(1-Y_M ))>U((1-x)Y_H )-U(s_w(1-Y_M ))\), the right-hand side decreases, leading to a contradiction. Thus, \(Y_H^{*}x^{*}>Y_H x\): an increase in the family’s income benefits both the husband and the wife. \(\square\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cohen, L., Glazer, A. Bargaining within the family can generate a political gender gap. Rev Econ Household 15, 1399–1413 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11150-015-9317-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11150-015-9317-6

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation