Skip to main content
Log in

Intrafamily bargaining and love

  • Published:
Review of Economics of the Household Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Popular culture and common wisdom testify that the way partners in a relationship feel for one another very much depends on how they treat each other. This paper posits the hypothesis that altruism or love in a relationship is endogenous to the actions of the partners and studies how this influences allocations and efficiency in a bargaining model of household decision-making. The main results are that agents treat their partner in a kinder way than without endogenously evolving love, this leads to more equitable allocations in household decision making and greater intertemporal efficiency. There are two mechanisms at work: agents treat their partner nicely to avoid retribution by a less loving partner in the future; and they treat the partner nicely so that the kind reciprocal behavior raises their own love towards the partner, which lets them enjoy higher utility. As to love, two interpretations emerge: love is a commitment device by which couples can implement Pareto superior allocations; and love is an investment good in the sense that costly nice behavior towards the partner today may ensure higher levels of trust and efficiency in the future.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As noted by Samuelson (1956), this model does not attempt explain how decision-making within households actually takes place.

  2. For a discussion see Grossbard (2010).

  3. See e.g. Becker (1965), Becker (1981), Pollak and Wachter (1975). A recent addition to this line of enquiry is given by Brown and Zhang (2013).

  4. See the discussion in Manser and Brown (1980) p. 34.

  5. The classic reference for psychological games is Geanakoplos et al. (1989). Their approach has been adapted to fairness (including reciprocity) in normal form games by Rabin (1993); extensions to sequential games can be found e.g. in Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger (2004) and Falk and Fischbacher (2006). For a recent exposition of altruistic feelings dependent on intentions see Cox et al. (2007).

  6. If agents are mortal and do not know the exact time of their death then their expectation can be modeled as an infinite life with a certain probability of death every period.

  7. In the evolution of love, I am abstracting from factors other the partner’s treatment. Other factors would for instance include the presence or absence of children as studied in Grossbard and Mukhopadhyay (2013).

  8. See Leece (2004) and van de Ven (2009) for similar interpretations of the BHPS data.

  9. For related empirical papers working on this question in the BHPS data see Powdthavee (2009) and Anand et al. (2005).

  10. This refers only to a relative shift in importance, not to any ranking in terms of well-being. For the latter, see e.g. Xiaohe and Whyte (1990) for an empirical investigation.

  11. This latter point is perhaps what separates the analysis of love from the one of friendship and affection.

References

  • Anand, P., Hunter, G., & Smith, R. (2005). Capabilities and well-being: Evidence based on the sen–nussbaum approach to welfare. Social Indicators Research, 74(1), 9–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basu, K. (2006). Gender and say: A model of household behaviour with endogenously determined balance of power. The Economic Journal, 116(511), 558–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1965). A theory of the allocation of time. The Economic Journal, 493–517.

  • Becker, G. (1973). A theory of marriage: Part I. The Journal of Political Economy, 81(4), 813–846.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1974). A theory of marriage: Part II. The Journal of Political Economy, 82(2), S11–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1974). A theory of social interactions. The Journal of Political Economy, 82(6), 1063–1093.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1981). A treatise on the family. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom, T. (1989). A fresh look at the rotten kid theorem—And other household mysteries. The Journal of Political Economy, 97(5), 1138–1159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bragstad, T. (1991). The private provision of a public good—The significance of thresholds. Mimeo: University of Oslo.

  • Brown, E., & Zhang, Y. (2013). Is volunteer labor part of household production? Evidence from married couples. Review of Economics of the Household, 11(3), 341–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browning, M. (2009). Love, betrayal and commitment. Mimeo: Oxford University.

  • Bruce, N., & Waldman, M. (1990). The Rotten-Kid theorem meets the Samaritan’s Dilemma. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 105(1), 155–165.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Cigno, A. (2012). Marriage as a commitment device. Review of Economics of the Household, 10(2), 193–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, J., Friedman, D., & Gjerstad, S. (2007). A tractable model of reciprocity and fairness. Games and Economic Behavior, 59(1), 17–45.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Dufwenberg, M. (2002). Marital investments, time consistency and emotions. Journal of Economic Behavior Organization, 48(1), 57–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dufwenberg, M., & Kirchsteiger, G. (2004). A theory of sequential reciprocity. Games and Economic Behavior, 47(2), 268–298.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., & Fischbacher, U. (2006). A theory of reciprocity. Games and Economic Behavior, 54(2), 293–315.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Geanakoplos, J., Pearce, D., & Stacchetti, E. (1989). Psychological games and sequential rationality. Games and Economic Behavior, 1(1), 60–79.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Grossbard, S. (2010). Independent individual decision-makers in household models and the new home economics. In J. Molina (Ed.), Household economic behaviors. New York: Springer.

  • Grossbard, S., & Mukhopadhyay, S. (2013). Children, spousal love, and happiness: an economic analysis. Review of Economics of the Household, 11(3), 447–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hess, G. (2004). Marriage and consumption insurance: What’s love got to do with it? Journal of Political Economy, 112(2), 290–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D. (1990). Team behavior in the family: An analysis of the Rotten Kid theorem. Bureau of Labor Statistics.

  • Kalai, E., & Smorodinsky, M. (1975). Other solutions to Nash’s bargaining problem. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 43(3), 513–518.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K., & Lommerud, K. (1995). Family policy with non-cooperative families. The Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 97(4), 581–601.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K., & Lommerud, K. (2000). The bargaining family revisited. Canadian Journal of Economics/Revue Canadienne d’économique, 33(2), 471–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K., Lommerud, K. (2008). Love and taxes mand matching institutions. Technical report, lCEPR Discussion paper.

  • Leece, D. (2004). Testing a theoretical model of mortgage demand on united kingdom data. Technical report, Citeseer.

  • Ligon, E. (2011). Dynamic bargaining in households (with application to Bangladesh). Working paper. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1776810 or doi:10.2139/ssrn.1776810.

  • Liu, X. (2007). Optimal dynamic path of effort on marriage: Differences between arranged and love marriages. Applied Economics Letters, 14(1), 49–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lundberg, S., & Pollak, R. (1993). Separate spheres bargaining and the marriage market. Journal of Political Economy, 101(6), 988–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lundberg, S., & Pollak, R. (1996). Bargaining and distribution in marriage. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 10(4), 139–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lundberg, S., & Pollak, R. (2003). Efficiency in marriage. Review of Economics of the Household, 1(3), 153–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manser, M., & Brown, M. (1980). Marriage and household decision-making: A bargaining analysis. International Economic Review, 21(1), 31–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McElroy, M., & Horney, M. (1981). Nash-bargained household decisions: Toward a generalization of the theory of demand. International Economic Review, 22(2), 333–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordblom, K. (2004). Cohabitation and marriage in a risky world. Review of Economics of the Household, 2(3), 325–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollak, R., & Wachter, M. (1975). The Relevance of the household production function and its implications for the allocation of time. The Journal of Political Economy, 83(2), 255–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Powdthavee, N. (2009). I cant smile without you: Spousal correlation in life satisfaction. Journal of Economic Psychology, 30(4), 675–689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (1993). Incorporating fairness into game theory and economics. The American Economic Review, 83(5), 1281–1302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. (1956). Social indifference curves. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 70(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van de Ven, J. (2009). A model of household savings and labour supply responses to the policy environment. Technical report, National Institute of Economic and Social Research.

  • Xiaohe, X., & Whyte, M. (1990). Love matches and arranged marriages: A Chinese replication. Journal of Marriage and the Family, 52(3), 709–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Man Si.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Derivation of best responses of i to j playing OF or W

1.1.1 Suppose j plays O

  • State Ii plays S:

    Agents will enter a cycle of alternating love such that total expected utility of i is \(U_{i,t}=\frac{(\beta+1)+\delta(2\beta+1)}{1-\delta^2}\).

 

α i,t

α j,t

w i,t

w j,t

u i,t

t

0

0

0

1

β + 1

t + 1

1

0

1

0

2β + 1

t + 2

0

1

0

1

β + 1

t + 3

1

0

1

0

2β + 1

  • State Ii plays O:

    Agents jump to the full love equilibrium within one period and total expected utility therefore is \(U_{i,t}=2\beta+\delta\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\).

 

α i,t

α j,t

w i,t

w j,t

u i,t

t

0

0

1

1

t + 1

1

1

1

1

t + 2

1

1

1

1

  • State Ii plays F:

    This leads the agents to the full love steady state, but takes longer than when i plays W. Total expected utility is \(U_{i,t}=(\beta+1)+\delta(2\beta+1)+\delta^22\beta+\delta^3\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\).

 

α i,t

α j,t

w i,t

w j,t

u i,t

t

0

0

0

1

β + 1

t+1

1

0

1

0

2β + 1

t+2

0

1

1

1

t+3

1

1

1

1

  • State Ii plays W:

    This leads to the same situation as when i plays O.

  • State IIIi plays S:

    The utility outcome is the same as in state I.

  • State IIIi plays O:

    The outcome is the same as for strategy S.

  • State IIIi plays F:

    The outcome is the same as for strategy W.

  • State IIIi plays W:

    The utility outcome is the same as in state I.

We can now construct a strategy ranking. For state I we have:

$$ S\succ F\;\Leftrightarrow\;\frac{(\beta+1)+\delta(2\beta+1)}{1-\delta^2} >(\beta+1)+\delta(2\beta+1)+\delta^22\beta+\delta^3\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\; \Leftrightarrow\;\delta<\hat{\delta}_{B1} $$
(9)
$$ F\succ\{O,W\}\;\Leftrightarrow\;(\beta+1)+\delta(2\beta+1)+\delta^22 \beta+\delta^3\frac{4\beta}{1-\beta}>2\beta+\delta\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\; \Leftrightarrow\;\delta<\hat{\delta}_{B2}=\hat{\delta}_{A2} $$
(10)

Where \(\hat{\delta}_{B1}=\frac{1-3\beta}{2\beta}+\sqrt{(\frac{1-3\beta}{2\beta})^2+ \frac{1-\beta}{\beta}}\). For state III we have:

$$ \{S,O\}\succ\{F,W\}\;\Leftrightarrow\;\frac{(\beta+1)+\delta(2\beta+1)} {1-\delta^2}>(\beta+1)+ \delta(2\beta+1)+\delta^22\beta+\delta^3 \frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\;\Leftrightarrow\; \delta<\hat{\delta}_{B3}=\hat{\delta}_{B1}. $$
(11)

1.1.2 Suppose j plays F

  • State Ii plays S:

    The outcome is the same as when j plays S and i plays S.

  • State Ii plays O:

    Here, within a couple of periods the agents reach the full love steady state, total expected utility is \(U_{i,t}=\beta+\delta(1+\delta)+\delta^2(2\beta+1)+\delta^3\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\).

 

α i,t

α j,t

w i,t

w j,t

u i,t

t

0

0

1

0

β

t + 1

0

1

0

1

β + 1

t + 2

1

0

1

1

2β + 1

t + 3

1

1

1

1

  • State Ii plays F:

    The outcome is the same as when j plays S and i plays S.

  • State Ii plays W:

    The outcome is the same as when j plays S and i plays W.

  • State IIIi plays S:

    Agents go to the full love equilibrium in two steps and total expected utility therefore is \(U_{i,t}=(\beta+1)+\delta(2\beta+1)+\delta^2\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\).

 

α i,t

α j,t

w i,t

w j,t

u i,t

t

0

1

0

1

β + 1

t + 1

1

0

1

1

2β + 1

t + 2

1

1

1

1

  • State IIIi plays O:

    The outcome is the same as if i played S.

  • State IIIi plays F:

    The outcome is the same as when j plays S and i plays F.

  • State IIIi plays W:

    The outcome is the same as when j plays S and i plays W.

The strategy ranking for state I can be constructed in two steps:

$$ \{S,F\}\succ O\;\Leftrightarrow\;\frac{1}{1-\delta}>\beta+\delta(1+ \delta)+\delta^2(2\beta+1)+\delta^3\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\;\Leftrightarrow\; \delta<\hat{\delta}_{C1} $$
(12)
$$ O\succ W\;\Leftrightarrow\;\beta+\delta(1+\delta)+\delta^2(2\beta+1)+ \delta^3\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}>\beta+\delta2\beta+\delta^2\frac{4 \beta}{1-\delta}\;\Leftrightarrow\; \delta<\hat{\delta}_{C2}=\frac{1-\beta}{2\beta-1} $$
(13)

Where \(\hat{\delta}_{C1}\) cannot be determined analytically. It can be shown numerically, however, that \(\hat{\delta}_{C1}>\hat{\delta}_{B1}\) for low levels of β and the other way around for high levels and that \(\hat{\delta}_{C1}<\hat{\delta}_{A1}\) for all levels of β.

For state III, the strategy ranking is the following:

$$ \{S,O\}\succ \{F,W\}\;\Leftrightarrow\;\beta+1+\delta(2\beta+1)+ \delta^2\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}>2\beta+\delta\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\; \Leftrightarrow\; \delta<\hat{\delta}_{C3}=\hat{\delta}_{C2}. $$
(14)

1.1.3 Suppose j plays W

  • State Ii plays S:

    Agents go to the full love equilibrium within two periods and total expected utility therefore is \(U_{i,t}=\beta+1+\delta\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}. \)

 

α i,t

α j,t

w i,t

w j,t

u i,t

t

0

0

0

1

β + 1

t+1

1

0

1

1

t+2

1

1

1

1

  • State Ii plays O:

    Agents jump to the full love equilibrium within one period and total expected utility therefore is \(U_{i,t}=2\beta+\delta\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\).

 

α i,t

α j,t

w i,t

w j,t

u i,t

t

0

0

1

1

t+1

1

1

1

1

  • State Ii plays F:

    The outcome is the same as when i plays S.

  • State Ii plays W:

    The outcome is the same as when i plays O.

  • State III:

    For strategies S and W the outcomes are the same as in state I. Here strategy O is equivalent to S and F is equivalent to W.

It is immediate that \(\beta+1+\delta\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\gtrless2\beta+\delta\frac{4\beta}{1-\delta}\) can be reduced to 1 > β which has been assumed.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Si, M. Intrafamily bargaining and love. Rev Econ Household 13, 771–789 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11150-014-9241-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11150-014-9241-1

keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation