Abstract
Salespersons often spend time and money giving prospective buyers compliments such as kind words, meals and gifts. Though prior research has shown that compliments will influence a prospective buyer’s decision, it is unknown the extent to which salespersons should make these investments. In this paper, we develop an analytical model to examine how seller and buyer characteristics affect the equilibrium provision of compliments by the seller. We establish that the optimal magnitude of compliments is non-monotonic in the buyer’s sensitivity to compliments. We identify conditions for when a seller of a high-quality product will offer greater (or lesser) compliments than a seller of a lower quality product. We show that, under certain conditions, an uninformed buyer earns greater utility than a buyer who knows the quality of the seller’s product. The findings have implications for sellers in their choice of compliments and buyers in the inferences they draw from the compliments received.
This is a preview of subscription content,
to check access.



Notes
We thank the editor for this note.
The assumption that T H >0 and T L ≤0 implies that the product quality of the low-type is not higher than that of the outside option whereas the product quality of the high-type is.
While this notation facilitates the exposition, in proofs of Lemmas 1 and 2, where we consider refinement conditions and out-of-equilibrium deviations, we will need to use the general form of the buyer’s belief defined as the probability z that the buyer thinks the seller is high-type given k.
D1 criterion is stronger than the more commonly used Intuitive criterion. However, in our model, Intuitive criterion requirement is not sufficient for uniquely identifying the equilibrium outcome. For an extended discussion of D1 criterion, please see Section 11.2 of Fudenberg and Tirole (1991).
Our game can easily shown to be a monotonic signaling game because all types prefer higher beliefs for being a high-type.
If \(\underline {\kappa }_{L} < 0\) and \({u_{L}^{X}}(0) < {u_{L}^{L}}(k_{L}^{\ast L})\), then no pure strategy Nash equilibrium exists. However, we can show that a mixing of the two mentioned separating and pooling equilibria forms a mixed strategy equilibrium. In particular, the high-type gives no compliment and the low-type mixes between giving no compliment and giving a compliment of magnitude \(k_{L}^{\ast L}\). In this equilibrium, the buyer’s belief is that the sender of a zero compliment is high-type with probability \(p^{\prime } > p\), and the sender of any non-zero compliment is low-type. Probability \(p^{\prime }\) and the mixing probability of the low-type are calculated from the low-type’s indifference condition between the two strategies.
SRI International and CBRE (http://sobc.cbre.com/ExchangingGiftsandEntertainment.html) are two examples.
In the parameter region such that there is a pooling equilibrium, the pooling occurs at k=0 and there will be no effect of a cap on k.
The weaker Intuitive criterion is sufficient for this part.
References
Acemoglu, D., & Verdier, T. (2000). The choice between market failures and corruption. The American Economic Review, 90(1), 194–211.
Aidt, T. (2003). Economic analysis of corruption: A survey. The Economic Journal, 113, F632–F652.
Akerlof, G. (1970). The market for ‘lemons’: Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84(3), 488–500.
Austen-Smith, D. (1987). Interest groups, campaign contributions, and probabilistic voting. Public choice, 54(2), 123–139.
Bagwell, K., & Riordan, M. (1991). High and declining prices signal product quality. American Economic Review, 81(2), 224–239.
Ball, R. (1995). Interest groups, influence and welfare. Economics and Politics, 7(2), 119–146.
Banks, J., & Sobel, J. (1987). Equilibrium selection in signaling games. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 55(3), 647–661.
Baron, D. (1989). Service-induced campaign contributions and the electoral equilibrium. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 104(1), 45–73.
Bennedsen, M., & Feldmann, S. (2001). Lobbying legislatures. Journal of Political Economy, 110(4), 919–946.
Bennedsen, M., & Feldmann, S. (2006). Informational lobbying and political contributions. Journal of Public Economics, 90(4), 631–656.
Blau, P. (1964). Exchange and Power in Social Life. New York: Wiley.
Burguet, R., & Che, Y. (2004). Competitive Procurement with Corruption. The RAND Journal of Economics, 35(1), 50–68.
Byrne, D., & Rhamey, R. (1965). Magnitude of Positive and Negative Reinforcements as a Determinant of Attraction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 2(6), 884–889.
Chamorro-Premuzic, T., Arteche, A., Bremner, A., Greven, C., & Furnham, A. (2010). Soft skills in higher education: importance and improvement ratings as a function of individual differences and academic performance. Educational Psychology, 30(2), 221–241.
Chan, E., & Sengupta, J. (2010). Insincere flattery actually works: A dual attitudes perspective. Journal of Marketing Research, 47(1), 122–133.
Chan, E., & Sengupta, J. (2013). Observing flattery: A social comparison perspective. Journal of Consumer Research, 40(4), 740–758.
Cho, I., & Sobel, J. (1990). Strategic stability and uniqueness in signaling games.Journal of Economic Theory, 50(2), 381–413.
Chu, W. (1992). Demand signaling and screening in channels of distribution. Marketing Science, 11(4), 327–347.
Cialdini, R., & Goldstein, N. (2004). Social influence: compliance and conformity. Annual Review of Psychology, 55(1), 591–621.
Cialdini, R., & Trost, M. (1998). Social influence: social norms, conformity, and compliance. In Gilbert, D.T., Fiske, S.T., & Lindzey, G. (Eds.), The Handbook of Social Psychology. 4th ed (pp. 2:151–92). Boston: McGraw-Hill.
Cropanzano, R., & Mitchell, M. (2005). Social exchange theory: An interdisciplinary review. Journal of Management, 31(6), 874–900.
Dwyer, R., Schurr, P., & Oh, S. (1987). Developing buyer-seller relationships. Journal of Marketing, 51(2), 11–27.
Emerson, R. (1976). Social exchange theory. Annual Review of Sociology, 2 (1), 335–362.
Frenzen, J., & Davis, H. (1990). Purchasing behavior in embedded markets. Journal of Consumer Rsearch), 17(1), 1–12.
Fudenberg, D., & Tirole, J. (1991). Game theory. 1991, (p. 393). Massachusetts: Cambridge.
Fugh-Berman, A., & Ahari, S. (2007). Following the script: How drug reps make friends and influence doctors. PLOS Medicine, 4(4). doi:10.1371/journal.pmed.0040150.
Gordon, R. (1996). Impact of ingratiation on judgments and evaluations: A meta-analytic investigation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71(1), 54–70.
Grant, N., Fabrigar, L., & Lim, H. (2010). Exploring the efficacy of compliments as a tactic for securing compliance. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 32(3), 226–233.
Grossman, G., & Helpman, E. (1994). Protection for sale. American Economic Review, 84(4), 833–850.
Grossman, G. M., & Helpman, E. (2001). Special interest politics. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Haytko, D. (2004). Firm-to-firm and interpersonal relationships: Perspectives from advertising agency account managers Journal of the Academy of Marketing Science, 32(3), 312–329.
Hertzendorf, M. (1993). I’m not a high-quality firm-but I play one on TV. RAND Journal of Economics, 24(2), 236–247.
Homans, G. (1958). Social behavior as exchange. American Journal of Sociology, 63(6), 697–606.
Homans, G. (1974). Social behavior, revised ed, (p. 25). New York: Harcourt-Brace.
Howard, D., Gengler, C., & Jain, A. (1995). What’s in a name A complimentary means of persuasion Journal of Consumer Research, 22(2), 200–211.
Iyer, G., & Kuksov, D. (2010). Consumer feelings and equilibrium product quality. Journal of Economics and Management Strategy, 19(1), 137–168.
Jiang, B., Ni, J., & Srinivasan, K. (2014). Signaling through pricing by service providers with social preferences. Marketing Science, 33(5), 641–654.
Jones, E. (1964). Ingratiation. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Liu, L., & Dukes, A. (2013). Consideration set formation with multiproduct firms: The case of within-firm and across-firm evaluation costs. Management Science, 59(8), 1871–1886.
Meeker, B.F. (1971). Decisions and exchange. American Sociological Review, 36(3), 485–495.
Miklos-Thai, J., & Zhang, J. (2013). (De)marketing to manage consumer quality inferences. Journal of Marketing Research, 50(1), 55–69.
Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1986). Price and advertising signals of product quality. The Journal of Political Economy, 94(4), 796–821.
Moorthy, S., & Srinivasan, K. (1995). Signaling quality with a money-back guarantee: The role of transaction costs. Marketing Science, 14(4), 442–466.
Musalem, A., & Joshi, Y. (2009). How much should you invest in each customer relationship? A competitive strategic approach. Marketing Science, 28(3), 555–565.
Nelson, P. (1974). Advertising as information. The Journal of Political Economy, 82(4), 729–754.
Nicholson, C., Compeau, L., & Sethi, R. (2001). The Role of interpersonal liking in building trust in long-term channel relationships. Journal of the Academy of Marketing Science, 29(1), 3–15.
Palmatier, R., Jarvis, C., Bechkoff, J., & Kardes, F. (2009). The role of customer gratitude in relationship marketing. Journal of Marketing, 73(5), 1–18.
Parasuraman, A., & Day, R. (1977). A management-oriented model for allocating sales effort. Journal of Marketing Research, 14(1), 22–33.
Price, L., & Arnould, E. (1999). Commercial friendships: Service provider-client relationships in context. Journal of Marketing, 63(4), 38–56.
Regan, D. (1971). Effects of a favor and liking on compliance. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 7(6), 627–639.
Rose-Ackerman, S. (1975). The economics of corruption. Journal of Public Economics, 4, 187–203.
Seiter, J. (2007). Ingratiation and gratuity: The effect of complimenting customers on tipping behavior in restaurants. Journal of Applied Social Pscyhology, 37(3), 478–485.
Seiter, J., & Dutson, E. (2007). The effects of compliments on tipping behavior in hairstyling salons. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 37(9), 1999–2007.
Spence, M. (1973). Job market signaling. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 87(3), 355–374.
Snyder, J. (1990). Campaign contributions As investments: The U.S. House of Representatives, 1980-1986. Journal of Political Economy, 98(6), 1195–1227.
Strutton, D., Pelton, L., & J. Tanner Jr (1996). Shall we gather in the garden: The effect of ingratiatory behaviors on buyer trust in salespeople Industrial Marketing Management, 25(2), 151–162.
Thibault, J., & Kelley, H. (1959). The Social Psychology of Groups. New York: Wiley.
Vonk, R. (2002). Self-serving interpretations of flattery: Why ingratiation works. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82(4), 515–526.
Zoltners, A., & Sinha, P. (1980). Integer programming models for sales resource allocation. Management Science, 26(3), 242–260.
Zoltners, A., Sinha, P., & Chong, P. (1979). An optimal algorithm for sales representative time management Management Science, 25(12), 1197–1207.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
University of Washington, Foster School of Business. Both authors contributed equally to this manuscript. Amin Sayedi (aminsa@uw.edu) is an Assistant Professor of Marketing and Jeffrey D. Shulman (jshulman@uw.edu) is the Marion B. Ingersoll Associate Professor of Marketing, both at Foster School of Business, University of Washington.
Appendix A: proofs of lemmas and propositions
Appendix A: proofs of lemmas and propositions
1.1 Proof of observation 1
The derivative of k ∗ with respect to α is
This is a decreasing function of α. Furthermore, it is strictly positive for \(\alpha = \frac {4c_{j}}{M}+\epsilon \), for sufficiently small 𝜖>0, and is strictly negative for α=1 (given that \(T_{j} < Arcosh\left (\frac {M}{2 c_{j}}-1\right )-\sqrt {\frac {M}{M - 4 c_{j}}}\) ). Therefore, there exists \(0 < \bar {\alpha } < 1\) for which this expression becomes zero. Though \(\bar {\alpha }\) does not have a closed-form solution, it is the unique solution to
Therefore, k ∗ is an increasing function of α for \(\alpha < \bar {\alpha }\), and a decreasing function of α for \(\alpha > \bar {\alpha }\).
When \(T_{j}> Arcosh\left (\frac {M}{2 c_{j}}-1\right )-\sqrt {\frac {M}{M - 4 c_{j}}}\), the derivative of k ∗ with respect to α is always positive.
1.2 Proof of proposition 1
First assume that c L >c H . Derivative of \(k_{H}^{\ast } - k_{L}^{\ast }\) with respect to M is
which is always negative. If \(M = \frac {4 c_{L}+\epsilon }{\alpha }\), for sufficiently small 𝜖>0, then \(\lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0}k_{H}^{\ast } - k_{L}^{\ast } = \frac {\Delta T (\alpha -1) + Arcosh(\frac {2 c_{L}}{c_{H}}-1)}{\alpha }\). This is positive if and only if \(\frac {c_{L}}{c_{H}} > \frac {1+Cosh({\Delta } T (1-\alpha ))}{2}\). We also have \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty }k_{H}^{\ast } - k_{L}^{\ast } = \frac {\Delta T (\alpha -1) + Log(\frac {\alpha }{c_{H}})-Log(\frac {\alpha }{c_{L}})}{\alpha }\). This is negative if and only if \(\frac {c_{L}}{c_{H}} < e^{\Delta T (1-\alpha )}\). In other words, \(\frac {c_{L}}{c_{H}} < e^{\Delta T (1-\alpha )}\) implies that as M grows, \(k_{H}^{\ast } - k_{L}^{\ast }\) becomes strictly negative. Therefore, when \(\frac {1+Cosh({\Delta } T (1-\alpha ))}{2} < \frac {c_{L}}{c_{H}} < e^{\Delta T (1-\alpha )} \), there exists a unique \(\bar {M}\) which is the solution to \(k_{H}^{\ast } = k_{L}^{\ast }\). \(\bar {M}\) does not have a closed-form solution; however, it is the unique solution to the following equation
If \(\frac {c_{L}}{c_{H}} \leq \frac {1+Cosh({\Delta } T (1-\alpha ))}{2}\), then \(k_{H}^{\ast } - k_{L}^{\ast }\) is always non-positive; and if \(\frac {c_{L}}{c_{H}} \geq e^{\Delta T (1-\alpha )}\), then \(k_{H}^{\ast } - k_{L}^{\ast }\) is always non-negative.
For the case where c L ≤c H , since k ∗ is a decreasing function of T j and a decreasing function of c j , we always have \(k_{H}^{\ast } \leq k_{L}^{\ast } \).
1.3 Proofs of lemmas 1 and 2
First, we prove that \(\bar {\kappa }_{H} \geq \bar {\kappa }_{L}\). This shows that the set of strategies in which the high-type gives compliments of magnitude \(\max (\bar {\kappa }_{L}, k_{H}^{\ast H})\) and the low-type give compliments of magnitude \(k_{L}^{\ast L}\) is a separating equilibrium.
To prove that \(\bar {\kappa }_{H} \geq \bar {\kappa }_{L}\), it suffices to show that \({u_{L}^{L}}(k_{L}^{\ast L}) \geq {u_{L}^{H}}(\bar {\kappa }_{H})\). Since \(k_{L}^{\ast L}\) is the value that maximizes \({u_{L}^{L}}(.)\), we know that
By expanding the right-hand-side, we get
Using the definition of \(\bar {\kappa }_{H}\), we can write this inequality as
Using the definition of \({u_{L}^{H}}\) and \({u_{H}^{H}}\), we have \({u_{H}^{H}}(k) = {u_{L}^{H}}(k) + k (c_{L} - c_{H})\) for any k. Therefore, we can write the above inequality as
Since \({u_{H}^{H}}(k) \geq {u_{H}^{L}}(k)\) for any k, we have \({u_{H}^{H}}(k_{H}^{\ast L}) \geq {u_{H}^{L}}(k_{H}^{\ast L})\). This implies that \(\bar {\kappa }_{H} \geq k_{H}^{\ast L}\). Therefore, the above inequality implies
This implies that \(\bar {\kappa }_{H} \geq \bar {\kappa }_{L}\), which completes the first part of the proof.
Next, we show that no other separating equilibrium can survive D1 criterion refinement. Given the definitions of \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) and \(\bar {\kappa }_{H}\), we know that there is no separating equilibrium in which the high-type gives compliments of magnitude lesser than \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\), otherwise, the low-type would benefit from deviating. Furthermore, according to D1 criterion refinement,Footnote 15 the weight of the buyer’s belief L must be zero for any compliments of magnitude at least \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\). Therefore, the high-type always gives compliments of magnitude \(\max (\bar {\kappa }_{L}, k_{H}^{\ast H})\) in any separating equilibrium that survives D1 criterion refinement. It is easy to see that the low-type gives compliments of magnitude \(k_{L}^{\ast L}\) in any separating equilibrium. Therefore, the only separating equilibrium that could possibly survive D1 criterion refinement is the one in which the high-type gives a compliment of magnitude \(\max (\bar {\kappa }_{L}, k_{H}^{\ast H})\) and the low-type gives a compliment of magnitude \(k_{L}^{\ast L}\).
Next, we prove that this equilibrium does survive D1 criterion refinement. We have already shown that the buyer’s belief on any compliments of magnitude greater than \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) is H. It remains to show that the buyer’s belief on any compliments of magnitude lesser than \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) is L. Consider a compliment of magnitude less than \(\kappa < \bar {\kappa }_{L}\), and suppose that the buyer’s belief is z>0, i.e., a seller who sends a compliment of size κ is high-type with probability z>0. Note that the low-type is indifferent between giving compliments of magnitude \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) and being perceived as high-type, and giving compliments of magnitude \(k_{L}^{\ast L}\) and being perceived as low-type. Therefore, a hypothetical deviation from \(k_{L}^{\ast L}\) to \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) leaves the utility of the low-type unchanged. Now, a deviation from compliments of magnitude \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) to compliments of magnitude κ has the same effect on probability of winning the contract (r(.)) for both types. However, the low-type gains more in terms of lowering the cost of compliment (since c H <c L ). Therefore, whenever such deviation is weakly profitable for the high-type, it is strictly profitable for the low-type. Therefore, according to D1 criterion, the buyer’s belief on out-of-equilibrium compliment κ must be L, i.e., z=0.
Finally, we show that no pooling equilibrium survives D1 criterion refinement. Assume for sake of contradiction that a pooling equilibrium exists. Let κ be the magnitude of compliments in this pooling equilibrium. For any k>κ, the high-type gains more (or loses less) by deviating to k, for any buyer’s belief weights on k, because c H <c L . Therefore, using D1 equilibrium refinement, the buyer’s belief on k must be H (i.e., someone using k must be high-type). In other words, since the high-type always gains more (or loses less) by increasing the magnitude of compliments, the buyer’s out-of-equilibrium belief about any compliments greater than κ must be high. Therefore, if k = κ + 𝜖 for sufficiently small 𝜖>0, both types benefit from deviating from κ to k because they get a discrete increase in their utility (by moving from belief X to belief H) but only lose c 𝜖 in terms of costs. This contradicts the equilibrium assumption.
The proof of Lemma 2 is very similar to that of Lemma 1. We can show that \(\underline {\kappa }_{H} < \underline {\kappa }_{L}\). Then, as long as \(\underline {\kappa }_{L} > 0\), the specified separating equilibrium exists. The proof of uniqueness subject to D1 criterion refinement is also very similar: the high-type always gains more (or loses less) by deviating to lesser compliments. Therefore, out-of-equilibrium beliefs on such deviations is always high. A pooling equilibrium could only exist if the magnitude of the compliment cannot be lowered, i.e., when both types give zero compliments.
1.4 Proof of proposition 2
Note that when c H <c L , the only equilibrium that survives D1 criterion refinement is a separating equilibrium. Therefore, in equilibrium, the buyer will rationally infer the sender’s type. The magnitude of compliments that sellers offer in the case of partial information is greater than or equal to that of full information case (low-type’s compliments are of the same magnitude, and high-type offers greater (or equal) compliments). Therefore, when c H <c L , the buyer’s utility in partial information setting is always greater than or equal to that of full information setting.
On the other hand, when c H >c L , the equilibrium is not always separating. Furthermore, the magnitude of compliments in partial information case is always less than or equal to that of full information case. Therefore, when c H >c L , the buyer is always (weakly) worse off when he does not know the seller’s type.
1.5 Proof of lemma 3
Note that when c H >c L we have \(\hat {k}_{H} = \min (\underline {\kappa }_{L}, k_{H}^{\ast H})\), and when c H <c L we have \(\hat {k}_{H} = \max (\bar {\kappa }_{L}, k_{H}^{\ast H})\). We already know that \(k_{H}^{\ast H}\) is an increasing function of M. It remains to be proven that \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) and \(\underline {\kappa }_{L}\) are increasing functions of M.
\(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) is defined as the solution \(\bar {\kappa }_{L}\) to
This equation expands to
for the case where \(K_{L}^{\ast L}=0\), and to
for the case where \(K_{L}^{\ast L} > 0\). If we take derivative of the first equation with respect to M we get
This implies that
It is easy to see that the numerator of the right hand side is negative; furthermore, given that we are considering the case where \(\bar {\kappa }_{L} \geq k_{H}^{\ast H}\) and c H <c L , using basic calculus we can show that the denominator of the right hand side is negative as well; therefore, \(\frac {\partial \bar {\kappa }_{L}}{\partial M}\) is positive. If we take the derivative of the second equation (the case where \(K_{L}^{\ast L} > 0\)) with respect to M, and use the same technique, we get
The denominator is the same as before, which we already know is negative. Given that we are considering the case where \(\bar {\kappa }_{L} \geq k_{H}^{\ast H}\), we can use basic calculus to show that the numerator is negative as well; therefore, \(\frac {\partial \bar {\kappa }_{L}}{\partial M}\) is positive. Finally, note that using the closed-form expression for \(k_{H}^{\ast H}\), it is easy to see that \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } k_{H}^{\ast H} = \infty \); therefore, we have \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } \hat {k}_{H} = \infty \) as well. This completes the proof for the case of c H <c L .
The analysis for the case of c L <c H is very similar. We have
By taking derivative of both sides with respect to M and rearranging the terms (same technique as before) we get
Using c H >c L and \(\underline {\kappa }_{L} \leq k_{H}^{\ast H}\) (because it is where \(\underline {\kappa }_{L}\) is relevant), it is easy to show that both the numerator and the denominator of the right hand side are positive. Therefore, \(\underline {\kappa }_{L}\) is an increasing function of M.
Next, we will prove that \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } \hat {k}_{H} = \infty \). Using basic calculus, it is easy to see that \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } \frac {{u_{L}^{L}}(k_{L}^{\ast L})} {M}= 1\). Therefore, using the definition of \(\underline {\kappa }_{L}\), we must have \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } \frac {{u_{L}^{H}}(\underline {\kappa }_{L})}{M}= 1\). But, using the definition of \({u_{L}^{H}}(.)\), this cannot happen if \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } \underline {\kappa }_{L} \) is bounded; therefore, we must have \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } \underline {\kappa }_{L} =\infty \). Also, using the closed-form expression for \(k_{H}^{\ast H}\) we already know that \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } k_{H}^{\ast H} = \infty \) as well; therefore, since \(\hat {k}_{H} = \min (\underline {\kappa }_{L}, k_{H}^{\ast H})\) we have \(\lim _{M \rightarrow \infty } \hat {k}_{H} = \infty \). This completes the proof for the case of c H >c L as well.
1.6 Proof of proposition 3
We first identify the values of M such that we can rule out the possibilities that the cap has a positive effect on the organization’s actual utility. If \(T_{L}<\alpha \hat {k}_{L}+(1-\alpha )T_{L}<p T_{H}+(1-p)T_{L}\), then the uncapped buying agent never uniquely makes Type I or Type II errors for low-type sellers. Given T L ≤0, the first inequality holds trivially for all \(\hat {k}_{L}\). From Lemmas 1 and 2, \(\hat {k}_{L}\) is a weakly increasing function of M, \(\hat {k}_{L}=0\) at M=0, and \(\hat {k}_{L} \rightarrow \infty \) as \(M \rightarrow \infty \). Thus, p>α is sufficient to ensure that \(\alpha \hat {k}_{L}+(1-\alpha )T_{L}<p T_{H}+(1-p)T_{L}\) at M=0 and there exists \(\hat {M}>0\) such that \(\alpha \hat {k}_{L}+(1-\alpha )T_{L}<p T_{H}+(1-p)T_{L}\) if and only if \(M<\hat {M}\).
If \(p T_{H}+(1-p)T_{L}<\alpha \hat {k}_{H}+(1-\alpha )T_{H}<T_{H}\), then the uncapped buying agent never uniquely makes Type I or Type II errors for high-type sellers. From Lemma 3, \(\hat {k}_{H}=0\) at M=0 and \(\hat {k}_{H}\) is weakly increasing in M. Therefore, there exists \(M^{\prime }\) such that \(\alpha \hat {k}_{H}+(1-\alpha )T_{H}<T_{H}\) is satisfied if and only if \(M<M^{\prime }\). The condition p<1−α is sufficient to ensure that \(p T_{H}+(1-p)T_{L}<\alpha \hat {k}_{H}+(1-\alpha )T_{H}\) for all M>0.
Therefore, if α<p<(1−α), then we can rule out the possibilities that allowing the buying agent to accept compliments has a negative effect on the organization’s actual utility for all \(M<\bar {M}\:= min(\hat {M},M^{\prime })\). Moreover, these conditions imply the ranges exist such allowing the buying agent to accept compliments has a positive effect on the objective buyer’s actual utility for 𝜖 satisfying \(\max \{-T_{H},-(\alpha \hat {k}_{H}+(1-\alpha )T_{H})\} < \epsilon < -(p T_{H}+(1-p )T_{L})\) or \(-(p T_{H}+(1-p )T_{L})<\epsilon <\min \{-T_{L}, -(\alpha \hat {k}_{L}+(1-\alpha )T_{L})\}\).
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Sayedi, A., Shulman, J.D. Strategic compliments in sales. Quant Mark Econ 15, 57–84 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11129-016-9177-2
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11129-016-9177-2