Skip to main content
Log in

Liberalism and democracy: legitimacy and institutional expediency

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper takes a closer look at how the relation between liberalism and democracy has been addressed by different strands of the liberal tradition. Its purpose is to argue in support of two claims. Firstly, the claim that discourse on what the two ideals are about, and how they are related to one another, has been impaired by a failure to pay due attention to the distinction between the question of legitimacy and the question of institutional expediency. Secondly, the claim that, when the noted distinction is taken into account, the two ideals can be shown to complement each other in their outlook at how social and political life should be organized.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. F.A. Hayek ([1966] 1967, p. 161) “Liberalism and democracy, although compatible, are not the same. The first is concerned with the extent of government, the second with who holds this power. The difference is best seen if we consider their opposites: the opposite of liberalism is totalitarianism, while the opposite of democracy is authoritarianism.”

  2. Buchanan ([1985] 2001, p. 271) speaks of the “presupposition that individuals are the only sources of value”.

  3. Such normative individualism is fundamentally opposed to any kind of external normative criterion that is claimed to allow for judgments on social matters independently of how the individuals involved themselves evaluate them, be it “the power of the nation”, “the will of god”, “historical destiny” or any other criterion that allows the holders of power to override the wishes of those they govern on account of their privileged insight into what the supposed standard requires.

  4. Buchanan ([1986] 1999, p. 467f.): “Normatively, the task of the political economist is to assist individuals, as citizens who ultimately control their own social order, in their continuing search for those rules of the political game that will serve their purposes, whatever these might be”.

  5. Buchanan (1975, p. 24): “Under regimes whose individual rights to do things are well defined and recognized, the free market offers maximal scope … for individual freedom in its most elementary meaning.”

  6. Buchanan ([1990] 1999, p. 392): “(T)he whole of the constitutional economic research program rests squarely on a democratic foundation.”.

  7. Hayek ([1973b] 1978, p. 109): “(T)he limitation of all coercion to the enforcement of general rules of just conduct was the fundamental principle of classical liberalism, or, I would almost say, its definition of liberty.”

  8. Hayek (1960, p. 158): “What exactly is to be included in that bundle of rights that we call ‚property ‘ … what contracts the state is to enforce, are all issues in which only experience will show what is the most expedient arrangement.”

  9. The ordo-liberal outlook at the state is covered more extensively in Köhler’s and Nientiedt’s contribution to this special issue.

  10. Such a government, Böhm ([1966] 1989, p. 66) notes, “is constantly faced with a considerable temptation to meet the contradictory demands of many pressure groups.… [T]his tendency … is a weakness of the system which must be taken seriously”.

  11. As Buchanan and Tullock (1962, p. 63ff.) detail in their “Generalized economic theory of constitutions”, the relative weight individuals will assign to “external costs” versus “decision-making costs” in choosing among alternative rules depends on the issue at stake. They will prefer more restrictive decision-making rules (qualified majority) for decisions on issues with potentially significant external costs, while they may be ready to accept simple majority rule for others. As Buchanan and Tullock (ibid., p. 72) note: “The rational individual at the stage of constitutional choice, confronts a calculus not unlike that which he must face in making his everyday choices. By agreeing to more inclusive rules, he is accepting the additional burden of decision-making in exchange for additional protection against adverse decisions. In moving in the opposing direction toward a less inclusive decision-making rule, the individual is trading some of his protection against external costs for a lowered cost of decision-making”.

  12. For a critical review see, e.g., Munger (2018) and G. Vanberg (2017).

  13. Incidentally, Nancy Maclean’s namesake, Iain McLean (1989, p. 34), states explicitly that “I define ‘democracy’ as ‘government by majority rule’” (McLean 1989, p. 34).

  14. In line with Rawls ‘s characterization of democratic society as a “cooperative venture”, one may speak, as I have suggested (Vanberg 2005, p. 41ff.), of democratic policies as citizens’ co-operatives or, in German as Bürgergenossenschaften. On the use of the term ‘Genossenschaft’ or ‘co-operative’ as labels for a democratic community, Vincent Ostrom (1991, p. 10) notes, “German-speaking Swiss still refer to the confederation as Eidgenossenschaft. Genossenschaft means association or comradeship. Eid refers to oath. An Eidgenossenschaft is an association bound together in a special commitment expressed by reciprocal oath. A Swiss citizen is referred as an Eidgenosse, that is, a covenantor – a comrade bound by oath. The source of authority resides, then, in a covenant that each is bound to uphold in governing relationships with another”.

  15. Hayek points out, though, that a difference in emphasis exists between the British and the continental liberal traditions: “Most of liberalism’s adherents would also profess a belief in individual freedom of action and in some sort of equality of all men, but … [w]hile to the older British tradition the freedom of the individual in the sense of a protection by law against all arbitrary coercion was the chief value, in the Continental tradition the demand for the self-determination of each group concerning its form of government occupied the highest place. This led to an early association and almost identification of the Continental movement with the movement of democracy, which is concerned with a different problem from that which was the chief concern of the liberal tradition of the British type” (Hayek [1973a] 1978, p. 120).

  16. Hayek ([1946] 1948, p. 29) adds: “Yet, while individualism affirms that all government should be democratic, it has no superstitious belief in the omnicompetence of majority decisions.” – On the source of the tension between the two ideals Hayek (fn. 21) refers to, Bellamy (1994, p. 419) comments that “The relationship between liberalism and democracy is notoriously paradoxical. On the one hand, the justification for democratic procedures most commonly rests on liberal assumptions.… On the other hand, liberal institutional arrangements … have frequently been interpreted as constraints on democracy”.

  17. Hayek (1960, p. 103) writes that “Equality before the law leads to the demand that all men should also have the same share in making the law. This is the point where traditional liberalism and the democratic movement meet.” Mises (1949, p. 271) refers to the common normative foundation of the ideals of liberalism and democracy when he notes that a “democratic constitution is a scheme to assign to citizens in the conduct of government the same supremacy the market gives them in their capacity as consumers,” and when he states that “Democracy is self-government, it is autonomy … Political democracy necessarily follows from liberalism” (Mises [1932] 1981, pp. 63, 65). See also Plattner (1998, p. 174): “Liberalism did not originally insist on democracy as a form of government, but it unequivocally insisted upon the ultimate sovereignty of the people”.

  18. “This means that the power of the majority is limited by those commonly held principles and there is no legitimate power beyond them … [T]he power of the majority ultimately derives from, and is limited by, the principles which the minority also accepts” (Hayek 1960, p. 107).

  19. “Thus, though the consistent application of liberal principles leads to democracy, democracy will preserve liberalism only, if, and so long as, the majority refrains from using its powers to confer on its supporters’ privileges which cannot be similarly offered to all citizens” (Hayek [1973a] 1978, p. 143).

  20. Hayek (1960: p. 103f.): “Its [liberalism’s] aim, indeed, is to persuade the majority to observe certain principles. It accepts majority rule as a method of deciding, but not as an authority for what the decision ought to be.” And furthermore, “Majority decisions tell us what people want at the moment, but not what it would be in their interest to want if they were better informed… True, there is the convention that the view of the majority should prevail so far as collective action is concerned, but this does not in the least mean that one should not make every effort to alter it. One may have profound respect for that convention and yet very little for the wisdom of the majority” (ibid., p. 109).

References

  • Bellamy, R. (1994). Dethroning politics: Liberalism, constitutionalism and democracy in the thought of F.A Hayek. . British Journal of Political Science, 24, 419–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Böhm, F. ([1966] 1989). The rule of law in a market economy. In A. Peacock, and H. Willgerodt (Eds.), Germany's social market economy: Origins and evolution, London: MacMillan, pp. 46–67.

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1958] 1999). Public principles and public debt: A defense and restatement. In G. Brennan (Ed.) The collected works of James M. Buchanan, (Vol 2), Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1960). Fiscal theory and political economy—Selected essays. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1967] 1999). The constitution of economic policy, in Buchanan. In G. Brennan, H. Kliemt, R.D. Tollison (Eds.) The logical foundations of constitutional liberty, The collected works of James M. Buchanan (Vol. 1, pp. 455–468). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1975). The limits of liberty—Between anarchy and Leviathan. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1977] 2001). A contractarian perspective on anarchy. In R.D. Tollison (Ed.) Buchanan, Choice, contract, and constitutions, The collected works of James M. Buchanan (vol 16, pp. 15–27). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1984] 2001). Opposition to constitutional reform. In R.D. Tollison (Ed.) Buchanan, Choice, contract, and constitutions, The collected works of James M. Buchanan (vol 16, pp. 356–371). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. [1985] (2001). Constitutional democracy, individual liberty, and political equality. In J.M. Buchanan, and H. Kliemt, (Ed.) Moral science and moral order, The collected works of James M. Buchanan, (vol. 17, pp. 266–280). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1986] 2001). Contractarianism and democracy. In R.D. Tollison (Ed.) Buchanan, Choice, contract, and constitutions, The collected works of James M. Buchanan, (vol 16, pp. 215–224). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1990] 1999). The domain of constitutional economics. In Buchanan, (pp. 377–395).

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1991] 1999). The foundations of normative individualism. In G. Brennan, H. Kliemt, R.D. Tollison (Eds.) Buchanan, The logical foundations of constitutional liberty, The collected works of James M. Buchanan, (vol. 1, pp. 281–291). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, St. (2001). Constitutionalizing inequality and the clash of globalization. International Studies Review, 4, 47–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haselbach, D. (1991). Autoritärer Liberalismus und Soziale Marktwirtschaft—Gesellschaft und Politik im Ordoliberalismus. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. ([1944] 2007). The road to serfdom. In B. Caldwell (Ed.) The collected works of F.A. Hayek, (vol. 2), Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Hayek, F.A. ([1946] 1948). Individualism: True and false. In Individualism and economic order, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Hayek, F. A. (1960). The constitution of liberty. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. ([1965] 2014). Kinds of rationalism. In: B. Caldwell, (Ed.) Markets and other order, The collected works of F.A. Hayek, (vol. 15, pp. 39–53). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Hayek, F.A. ([1966] 1967). The principles of a liberal social order, in: Studies in philosophy, politics and economics, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, (pp. 160–177).

  • Hayek, F. A. (1967). Notes on the evolution of systems of rules of conduct (The interplay between rules of individual conduct and the social order of actions). Studies in philosophy, politics and economics (pp. 66–81). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1973). Law, legislation and liberty, rules and order (Vol. 1). London and Henley: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. ([1973a] 1978). Liberalism. In New studies in philosophy, politics, economics and the history of ideas, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, (pp.119–151).

  • Hayek, F.A. ([1973b] 1978). Economic freedom and representative government. In New studies in philosophy, politics, economics and the history of ideas, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, (pp. 105–118).

  • Hayek, F. A. (1979). Law, legislation and liberty, The political order of a free people (Vol. 3). London and Henley: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hoppe, H.-H. (1998). Introduction. In M.N. Rothbard (Ed.) The ethics of liberty, (pp. xi–xliii). New York and London: New York University Press.

  • Hoppe, H.-H. (2001). Democracy—The god that failed. New Brunswick and London: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G. (1988). Wirtschaftspolitik und Politiksystem: Zur Kritik der traditionellen Ordnungstheorie aus der Sicht der Neuen Politischen Ökonomie. In D. Cassel, BTh. Ramb, & H. J. Thieme (Eds.), Ordnungspolitik (pp. 53–75). München: Vahlen.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacLean, N. (2017). Democracy in chains—The deep history of the radical right’s stealth plan for America. Melbourne and London: Scribe.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. (1989). Democracy and the new technology. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munger, C. M. (2018). On the origins and goals of Public Choice—Constitutional conspiracy? In The Independent Review 22, n. 3, Winter 2018, 359–382 (https://polisci.duke.edu/news/georg-vanberg-and-michael-munger-respond-democracy-chains).

  • Ostrom, V. (1981). American federalism—Constituting a self-governing society. San Francisco: Institute for Contemporary Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plattner, M. F. (1998). Liberalism and democracy—Can’t have one without the other. Foreign Affairs, 77, 171–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. ([1985] 1999). Justice as fairness: Political not metaphysical. In S. Freeman (Ed.) Collected papers. (pp. 388–414). Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

  • Rawls, J. ([1997] 1999). The idea of public reason revisited. In S. Freeman (Ed.) Collected papers. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, pp. 573–615.

  • Reinhoudt, J., & Audier, S. ([1938] 2018). The Walter Lippman colloquium—The birth of neo-liberalism, London: Palgrave MacMillan.

  • Rothbard, M. N. (1970). Man, economy, and state – A treatise on economic principles. Los Angeles: Nash Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothbard, M. N. ([1973] 2002). For a new liberty: The libertarian Manifesto, rev., Auburn: Ludwig von Mises Institute.

  • Rothbard, M. N. ([1982] 1998). The ethics of liberty. New York: New York University Press.

  • Samet, D., & Schmeidler, D. (2003). Between liberalism and democracy. Journal of Economic Theory, 110, 213–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, G. (2017). Duke professor Georg Vanberg on ‘Democracy in chains’. In The Washington Post, July 14, 2017 (https://polisci.duke.edu/news/georg-vanberg-and-michael-munger-respond-democracy-chains).

  • Vanberg, G. (2018). Constitutional political economy, democratic theory and institutional design. Public Choice, 177, 199–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1994). Cultural evolution, collective learning and constitutional design. In D. Reisman (Ed.), Economic thought and political theory (pp. 171–204). Dordrecht: Boston.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1998). Freiburg school of law and economics. In P. Newman (Ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law (Vol. 2, pp. 172–179). London: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (2005). Market and state: the perspective of constitutional political economy. Journal of Institutional Economics, 1, 23–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (2014). Darwinian paradigm, cultural evolution and human purposes: On F.A. Hayek’s evolutionary view of the market. Journal of Evolutionary Economics, 24, 35–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L. ([1932] 1981). Socialism—An economic and sociological analysis. Indianapolis: Liberty Clasics.

  • von Mises, L. (1949). Human action—A treatise on economics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L. (1957). Theory and history. An interpretation of social and economic evolution. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Viktor J. Vanberg.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vanberg, V.J. Liberalism and democracy: legitimacy and institutional expediency. Public Choice 195, 251–268 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-021-00873-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-021-00873-2

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation