Skip to main content
Log in

Risk aversion and bandwagon effect in the pivotal voter model

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The empirical literature on the effects of opinion polls on election outcomes has recently found substantial evidence of a bandwagon effect, defined as the phenomenon according to which the publication of opinion polls is advantageous to the candidate with the greatest support. This result is driven, in the lab experiments, by a higher turnout rate among the majority than among the minority. Such evidence is however in stark contrast with the main theoretical model of electoral participation in public choice, the pivotal voter model, which predicts that the supporters of an underdog candidate participate at a higher rate, given the higher probability of casting a pivotal vote. This paper tries to reconcile this discrepancy by showing that a bandwagon effect can be generated within the pivotal voter model by concavity in the voters’ utility function, which makes electoral participation more costly for the expected loser supporters. Given the strict relationship between concavity and risk aversion, the paper also establishes the role of risk aversion as a determinant of bandwagon.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Such as the majority rule system that I consider in the following sections, but also a proportional representation system (Kartal 2015).

  2. The studies by Levine and Palfrey (2007) and Herrera et al. (2014) find, however, higher turnout rates among the minority than the majority.

  3. Two other possible explanations have been proposed: Hong and Konrad (1998) argue that bandwagon can be caused by aversion to the uncertainty associated with an election; Morton and Ou (2015) study the possible role of other-regarding motives.

  4. Solutions to the so-called paradox of voting include introducing ethical (or group-utilitarian) voters (Coate and Conlin 2004; Feddersen and Sandroni 2006; Evren 2012), assuming that mandate matters for the implementation of the winning platform after the election (Castanheira 2003), or introducing aggregate uncertainty about candidates’ support (Myatt 2015). For a survey on voter turnout models and a comparison between the pivotal voter and the ethical voter models, see Merlo (2006).

  5. However, it should be noticed that an important assumption for the underdog result is the presence of uncertainty concerning the preferences of the electorate. Indeed, a bandwagon effect may in some cases be compatible with the standard pivotal voter model under the assumption that the supporters’ group size is known with certainty. This is often the case in lab experiments, where the majority and minority group sizes are held fixed in order to make the experiment easier to understand for the participants. The evidence of bandwagon is however much greater than the one that could be explained by such cases.

  6. Clearly, I assume \(q+p\,\le\, 1\).

  7. In the online supplementary material (Sect. 2), I propose a graphical representation of the decision-theoretic model through the analysis of Eq. (2).

  8. Indeed, if \(u(x)=x\), then \((q+p)(B-c)+(1-q-p)(-c)>q(B)+(1-q)0\Rightarrow pB>c\). Riker and Ordeshook (1968) derive (1) from (2) but do not discuss the underlying hypothesis of linearity.

  9. The fact that people are more likely to vote in elections that they deem more important is well-established. This is not a peculiar prediction of the pivotal voter model, which is characterized by the claim that the effect of B on the agent’s decision is discounted by the probability of being pivotal.

  10. The assumption of heterogeneity in voting costs turns out to be a crucial one for a bandwagon result. In the online supplementary material (Sect. 3), I show that in the presence of homogeneous costs of voting the model would yield the same full underdog result as in the standard linear pivotal voter model.

  11. With respect to the previous section, I change the subscripts from w (winner) and l (loser) to b (bigger) and s (smaller) because in the game-theoretic model, even if candidate 1 has a larger group of supporters, the expected winning candidate is determined by the turnout rates.

  12. In fact, the solution of system (9) is unique in all my numerical computations.

  13. The value 1.54 might seem very high compared to the usual estimates of an absolute risk-aversion parameter, but it comes from the fact that I only evaluate the utility function in the small range (−c, 1) with \(c\in (0, \, 1)\). My numerical computations show that Proposition 8(i) would still be true if I specify a constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) utility function (bound by 1 to the left to make sure that the numerator is positive, i.e. \(u(x)=\frac{(x+1)^{1-\gamma }}{1-\gamma }\)), instead of a CARA function. In this case, the threshold for the relative risk-aversion parameter would be approximately equal to 1.77, which is lower than its usual estimates. For an agent with an absolute risk-aversion parameter equal to 1.54, the certainty equivalent of a lottery that yields a payoff of either 1 or 0 both with probability one-half is 0.32.

  14. With two agents, the expected number of candidate 1 supporters is \(2\pi\) (\({>}1\)) and the expected number of candidate 2 supporters is \(2(1-\pi )\) (\({<}1\)).

  15. Owing to computational difficulties, I have run simulations only for \(n\le 250\).

  16. They disappear for higher values of \(\pi\), lower values of n and higher and lower values of \(\gamma\).

  17. However, for extreme values of \(\pi\) (e.g., \(\pi =0.95\)), my computations show that \(\bar{\gamma }(n)\) is first decreasing and then again increasing in n.

  18. For an agent with a constant absolute risk aversion parameter equal to 0.27, the certainty equivalent of a lottery that yields a payoff of either 1 or 0 both with probability one-half is 0.47.

References

  • Agranov, M., Goeree, J. K., Romero, J. & Yariv, L. (2015). What makes voters turn out: The effects of polls and beliefs. Working Paper.

  • Banerjee, A. V. (1992). A simple model of herd behavior. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107(3), 797–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blais, A. (2000). To vote or not to vote? The merits and limits of rational choice theory. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Börgers, T. (2004). Costly voting. The American Economic Review, 94(1), 57–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callander, S. (2007). Bandwagons and momentum in sequential voting. The Review of Economic Studies, 74(3), 653–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castanheira, M. (2003). Victory margins and the paradox of voting. European Journal of Political Economy, 19(4), 817–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coate, S., & Conlin, M. (2004). A group rule-utilitarian approach to voter turnout: Theory and evidence. The American Economic Review, 94(5), 1476–1504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cukierman, A. (1991). Asymmetric information and the electoral momentum of public opinion polls. Public Choice, 70(2), 181–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duffy, J., & Tavits, M. (2008). Beliefs and voting decisions: A test of the pivotal voter model. American Journal of Political Science, 52(3), 603–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evren, Ö. (2012). Altruism and voting: A large-turnout result that does not rely on civic duty or cooperative behavior. Journal of Economic Theory, 147(6), 2124–2157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T., & Sandroni, A. (2006). A theory of participation in elections. The American Economic Review, 96(4), 1271–1282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goeree, J. K., & Grosser, J. (2007). Welfare reducing polls. Economic Theory, 31(1), 51–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grosser, J., & Schram, A. (2010). Public opinion polls, voter turnout, and welfare: An experimental study. American Journal of Political Science, 54(3), 700–717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrera, H., Morelli, M., & Palfrey, T. (2014). Turnout and power sharing. The Economic Journal, 124(574), F131–F162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, R., & Maloney, J. (2013). Bandwagon effects in british elections, 1885–1910. Public Choice, 157(1–2), 73–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hong, C. S., & Konrad, K. (1998). Bandwagon effects and two-party majority voting. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 16(2), 165–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, G. A. & Van Holsteyn, J. J. M. (2000). Bandwagons, underdogs, the titanic, and the red cross. The influence of public opinion polls on voters. In Communication presented at the 18th congress of the international political science association, Quebec, requested from the authors.

  • Kam, C. D. (2012). Risk attitudes and political participation. American Journal of Political Science, 56(4), 817–836.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kartal, M. (2015). A comparative welfare analysis of electoral systems with endogenous turnout. The Economic Journal, 125(587), 1369–1392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiss, Á., & Simonovits, G. (2014). Identifying the bandwagon effect in two-round elections. Public Choice, 160(3–4), 327–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klor, E. F., & Winter, E. (2007). The welfare effects of public opinion polls. International Journal of Game Theory, 35(3), 379–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krasa, S., & Polborn, M. K. (2009). Is mandatory voting better than voluntary voting? Games and Economic Behavior, 66(1), 275–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ledyard, J. O. (1984). The pure theory of large two-candidate elections. Public Choice, 44(1), 7–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, D. K., & Palfrey, T. R. (2007). The paradox of voter participation? A laboratory study. American Political Science Review, 101(1), 143–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lott, J. R. (2005). The impact of early media election calls on Republican voting rates in Florida’s western Panhandle counties in 2000. Public Choice, 123(3–4), 349–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, C. (1985). Back on the bandwagon: The effect of opinion polls on public opinion. British Journal of Political Science, 15(1), 51–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, I., & Studlar, D. T. (1991). Bandwagon, underdog, or projection? Opinion polls and electoral choice in Britain, 1979–1987. Journal of Politics, 53(3), 720–741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D., & Ordeshook, P. C. (1985). Elections with limited information: A fulfilled expectations model using contemporaneous poll and endorsement data as information sources. Journal of Economic Theory, 36(1), 55–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merlo, A. (2006). Whither political economy? Theories, facts and issues. In R. Blundell, W. Newey & T. Persson (Eds.), Advances in economics and econometrics, theory and applications: ninth world congress of the econometric society.

  • Morton, R. B., & Ou, K. (2015). What motivates bandwagon voting behavior: Altruism or a desire to win? European Journal of Political Economy, 40, 224–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, R. B., Muller, D., Page, L., & Torgler, B. (2015). Exit polls, turnout, and bandwagon voting: Evidence from a natural experiment. European Economic Review, 77, 65–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myatt, D. (2015). A theory of voter turnout. Working paper.

  • Nadeau, R., Cloutier, E., & Guay, J. H. (1993). New evidence about the existence of a bandwagon effect in the opinion formation process. International Political Science Review, 14(2), 203–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T. R., & Rosenthal, H. (1983). A strategic calculus of voting. Public Choice, 41(1), 7–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T. R., & Rosenthal, H. (1985). Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. American Political Science Review, 79(1), 62–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H., & Ordeshook, P. C. (1968). A theory of the calculus of voting. American Political Science Review, 62(1), 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shachar, R., & Nalebuff, B. (1999). Follow the leader: Theory and evidence on political participation. American Economic Review, 89(3), 525–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1954). Bandwagon and underdog effects and the possibility of election predictions. Public Opinion Quarterly, 18(3), 245–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. R., & Yildirim, H. (2010a). Public information and electoral bias. Games and Economic Behavior, 68(1), 353–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. R., & Yildirim, H. (2010b). A unified analysis of rational voting with private values and group-specific costs. Games and Economic Behavior, 70(2), 457–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Philippe De Donder, Helios Herrera, Richard Johnston, Elia Lapenta, Michel Le Breton, Massimo Morelli, François Salanié, Karine Van Der Straeten, seminar participants at TSE, the participants to the 2nd Leuven-Montreal Winter School on Elections and Voting Behavior, and the participants to the 2016 Enter Jamboree in Madrid for their useful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alberto Grillo.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (pdf 240 KB)

Expressions for \(p_{1}\), \(p_{2}\) and q

Expressions for \(p_{1}\), \(p_{2}\) and q

I derive here the expressions for \(p_{1}\), \(p_{2}\) and q in system (6). For the calculation of \(p_{1}\) and \(p_{2}\), I draw on the analysis in Goeree and Grosser (2007). An agent is pivotal only when either the rest of the voting agents is equally split between the two candidates (turning a draw into a victory) or when the opposing candidate would win by one vote if the agent abstains (turning a loss into a draw). Given the tie-breaking rule in the case of a draw, in both cases the probability of being pivotal is divided by one-half. Clearly the first scenario can happen if the number of other voters is even, while the second if such number is odd. The two cases can be combined using the floor operator \(\lfloor {\cdot }\rfloor\). Consider first a supporter of candidate 1, supposing that k other agents also prefer candidate 1, \(n-k-1\) prefer candidate 2 and a total of l agents vote. Assuming that the cutoff costs \(c_{b}\) and \(c_{s}\) are both in (0, 1), the probability of being pivotal \(p_{1}\) is equal to

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned}p_{1}(c_{b},c_{s})=\frac{1}{2}\sum \limits _{l=0}^{n-1}\sum \limits _{k=\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\rfloor }^{n-1-\lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor }\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \pi ^{k}(1-\pi )^{n-k-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}k\\ \left\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\right\rfloor \end{array}}\right) \left( {\begin{array}{c}n-k-1\\ \lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor \end{array}}\right) \\ \times (c_{b})^{\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\rfloor }(1-c_{b})^{k-\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\rfloor }(c_{s})^{\lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor }(1-c_{s})^{n-k-1-\lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor } \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Analogously for a supporter of candidate 2, the probability of being pivotal \(p_{2}\) is equal to

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned}p_{2}(c_{b},c_{s})=\frac{1}{2}\sum \limits _{l=0}^{n-1}\sum \limits _{k=\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\rfloor }^{n-1-\lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor }\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) (1-\pi )^{k}\pi ^{n-k-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}k\\ \lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\rfloor \end{array}}\right) \left( {\begin{array}{c}n-k-1\\ \lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor \end{array}}\right) \\ \times (c_{s})^{\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\rfloor }(1-c_{s})^{k-\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}}\rfloor }(c_{b})^{\lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor }(1-c_{b})^{n-k-1-\lfloor {\frac{l+1}{2}}\rfloor } \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(12)

In addition to \(p_{1}\) and \(p_{2}\), I need to calculate the probability q, which emerges in the agent’s decision problem if the assumption of linearity in the utility function is relaxed. To do so, notice that when l other agents vote, candidate 1 wins if at least \(\frac{l}{2}+1\) agents vote for him for l even, or at least \(\frac{l+1}{2}\) for l odd. The two cases can again be combined using the floor operator: if l agents vote, candidate 1 wins if at least \(\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}+1}\rfloor\) vote for him. Moreover, by the assumption on the tie-breaking, candidate 1 also wins with probability one-half if the voters are equally split between the two candidates (l must be even). Hence, assuming \(c_{b}\) and \(c_{s}\) both in (0, 1), q is equal to

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned}q(c_{b},c_{s})=\sum \limits _{l=0}^{n-1}\sum \limits _{k=v}^{n-1-l+v}\sum \limits _{v=\lfloor {\frac{l}{2}+1}\rfloor }^{l}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \pi ^{k}(1-\pi )^{n-k-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}k\\ v\end{array}}\right) \left( {\begin{array}{c}n-k-1\\ l-v\end{array}}\right) \\ \times (c_{b})^{v}(1-c_{b})^{k-v}(c_{s})^{l-v}(1-c_{s})^{n-k-1-l+v}\\ +\,\frac{1}{2}\sum \limits _{l\text { even, }l=0}^{n-1}\sum \limits _{k=\frac{l}{2}}^{n-1-\frac{l}{2}}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \pi ^{k}(1-\pi )^{n-k-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}k\\ \frac{l}{2}\end{array}}\right) \left( {\begin{array}{c}n-k-1\\ \frac{l}{2}\end{array}}\right) \\ \times (c_{b})^{\frac{l}{2}}(1-c_{b})^{k-\frac{l}{2}}(c_{s})^{\frac{l}{2}}(1-c_{s})^{n-k-1-\frac{l}{2}} \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(13)

The probabilities \(p_{1}\), \(p_{2}\) and q are strictly positive also in the case that \(c_{b}\) or \(c_{s}\) are equal to zero (see the proof of Proposition 6 in the online supplementary material). In particular, \(p_{1}=p_{2}=q=\frac{1}{2}\) if \(c_{b}=c_{s}=0\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Grillo, A. Risk aversion and bandwagon effect in the pivotal voter model. Public Choice 172, 465–482 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-017-0457-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-017-0457-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation