Abstract
The counterfactual comparative account of harm faces problems in cases that involve overdetermination and preemption. An influential strategy for dealing with these problems, drawing on a suggestion made by Derek Parfit, is to appeal to plural harm—several events together harming someone. We argue that the most well-known version of this strategy, due to Neil Feit, as well as Magnus Jedenheim Edling’s more recent version, is fatally flawed. We also present some general reasons for doubting that the overdetermination and preemption problems for the counterfactual comparative account can be satisfactorily solved by appealing to plural harm.
1 Introduction
Adherents of the counterfactual comparative account of harm (CCA) often acknowledge that this account has problematic implications in cases of overdetermination and preemption. Some have tried to modify CCA in order to better handle such cases (Bradley 2009: 52–60; Hanna 2016; Immerman 2022; McMahan 2002: 128; Norcross 2005). Drawing on a suggestion made by Parfit (1984: 70–72), others have argued that CCA is correct in its standard form, and that the overdetermination and preemption problems can be solved by generalizing the account, so as to cover pluralities of events in addition to singular events. The most well-known such CCA-friendly account of “plural harm” is that of Neil Feit (2015; see also Feit 2022).Footnote 1 Recently, Magnus Jedenheim Edling (2022) has put forward a variant of Feit’s account.Footnote 2 In this paper, we shall argue that both Feit’s and Jedenheim Edling’s accounts are fatally flawed. We shall also present some general reasons for doubting that the overdetermination and preemption problems for CCA can be satisfactorily solved by appealing to plural harm.
2 CCA and the plural harm approach
As usually formulated, CCA applies only to singular events:
CCA
An event e harms a person S if and only if S would have been better off had e not occurred.Footnote 3
Problematically, CCA cannot account for the harm that apparently occurs in cases like the following:
Two Shooters
X and Y simultaneously, and independently of each other, shoot and kill Z. Either shot, by itself, would have been fatal. (Cf. Feit 2015: 362; Parfit 1984: 70)
CCA implies that neither shooting harms Z. A more intuitive judgment is that each shooting does. According to advocates of the plural harm approach, however, we can at least say something similar to this while still accepting CCA—namely, that Z is harmed by the plurality of X’s and Y’s shootings.
Proponents of the plural harm approach emphasize (e.g., Feit 2015: 370) that in this context, speaking of a “plurality” of two or more events is just a way of speaking about them; the plurality is neither a composite object with those events as parts, nor a set with those events as members. Moreover, to say that a plurality of events “harms” a person S is not to say that each of those events harms S—it is to say that those events harm S together. (In the standard jargon, ‘harms’ should be given a “collective” rather than a “distributive” reading.) This is analogous to how some pearls may together form a circle even though no individual pearl forms a circle. As Feit puts it, the idea is that “some basic facts about harm are irreducibly plural” (2015: 370).
We shall follow Feit and Jedenheim Edling in speaking of “subpluralities” of other pluralities. It should be borne in mind that every way of “partitioning” a plurality into subpluralities yields the very same plurality. Thus, using ‘[…]’ to denote a plurality, there is no distinction between the pluralities [e, e*, e**], [[e, e*], [e**]], and [[e], [e*, e**]]. They are all just the three events e, e*, and e**, referred to collectively. Further, every singular event is a plurality of itself, and every plurality is a subplurality of itself (although not a “proper” one).
Returning to Two Shooters, a natural suggestion, at least for proponents of CCA, is that the plurality of X’s shooting and Y’s shooting harms Z because Z would have been better off if neither event had occurred. As is often pointed out, however, a plurality of events being such that S would have been better off had none of the events in it occurred does not seem sufficient for the plurality’s harming S. Such a plurality may include events that are intuitively irrelevant to the harm done. It would be implausible to claim, for example, that Z is harmed by the plurality consisting of X’s shooting, Y’s shooting, and the entirely unrelated event of a certain blackbird’s singing (see, e.g., Parfit 1984: 71). The following account of plural harm incorporates the obvious solution to this problem:
The Minimal Plurality Account (MPA)
A plurality of events E harms S if and only if (i) S would have been better off had none of the events in E occurred, and (ii) there is no proper subplurality of E such that S would have been better off had none of the events in it occurred.
MPA implies that the plurality [X’s shooting, Y’s shooting, the blackbird’s singing] does not harm Z, since it has a proper subplurality, viz., [X’s shooting, Y’s shooting], which is such that Z would have been better off had neither event in it occurred. Since the one-event plurality [e] is the same thing as the event e, and [e] is harmful according to MPA just in case e is harmful according to CCA, MPA entails CCA. (In particular, note that any one-event plurality trivially satisfies MPA’s condition (ii).) Of course, since CCA, unlike MPA, is silent on when pluralities of more than one event are harmful, the reverse entailment does not hold. MPA is thus an extension of CCA.
3 Feit’s GPH and why it fails
Feit would, we think, consider MPA to be on the right track, but not quite accurate. He discusses an account, labeled ‘PH’ (Feit 2015: 371), which resembles MPA, and finds it wanting in certain respects. One of his objections to PH pertains also to MPA. Consider the following case:
Three Shooters
X, Y, and U simultaneously, and independently of each other, shoot and kill Z. Each pair of shots would have been fatal, but no single shot would, by itself, have killed (or even injured) Z.
In this case, MPA implies that there are three harmful pluralities, viz., [X’s shooting, Y’s shooting], [X’s shooting, U’s shooting], and [Y’s shooting, U’s shooting]. The plurality of all three shootings, on the other hand, does not satisfy clause (ii), and hence it does not harm Z according to MPA. Feit would reject this result, and claim that also the latter plurality harms Z.Footnote 4 This is the result yielded by Feit’s account General Plural Harm, or GPH (2015: 376). Let an ‘MPA-harm’ for S be a plurality that harms S according to MPA. (Occasionally, we shall also use ‘MPA-harm’ as a verb, with the corresponding meaning.) GPH can then be stated as follows:
General Plural Harm (GPH)
A plurality of events E harms S if and only if E is an MPA-harm, or a plurality of MPA-harms, for S.Footnote 5
GPH, just like MPA, entails CCA. (As we shall see in the next section, Feit goes on to slightly revise GPH.)
An immediate implication of GPH is that any plurality of harmful pluralities is itself harmful. In other words, GPH (unlike MPA) entails
Agglomeration
If each of two pluralities E and E* harms S, the plurality [E, E*] also harms S.
This allows for the possibility that a plurality harms a person, according to GPH, although she would have been worse off if no event in the plurality had occurred. The following is a case in point:
Painkillers
Z has a terrible headache and hence takes two painkillers, A and B. The pills fully relieve his headache but cause a somewhat unpleasant heartburn. A single pill would have fully relieved his headache without causing a heartburn. Z would have taken pill A even if he had not taken pill B, and he would have taken pill B even if he had not taken pill A.
The events Z’s taking pill A and Z’s taking pill B are both CCA-harms, and hence MPA-harms, for Z. GPH thus implies that the plurality of the two events also harms him. Whether this result is problematic is somewhat unclear. On the one hand, it seems to conflict with the core idea behind MPA and GPH, since the plurality leaves Z better off overall than he would have been had neither event occurred. On the other hand, the result may nonetheless be defensible, in view of the fact that taking only one pill would have left Z even better off.Footnote 6
Whatever one thinks about the harmfulness of this plurality, Painkillers also illustrates a much more serious problem for GPH. Although Feit does not explicitly formulate any account of plural benefit, it is clear that he accepts the widespread and attractive idea that benefit is, so to speak, the converse of harm (see, e.g., Feit 2015: 370, 380–381; 2016: 139; 2022).Footnote 7 According to this idea, MPA is easily supplemented so as to give an account also of plural benefit:
MPA
A plurality of events E harms (benefits) S if and only if (i) S would have been better (worse) off had none of the events in E occurred, and (ii) there is no proper subplurality of E such that S would have been better (worse) off had none of the events in it occurred.
Supplemented accordingly, GPH says that a plurality E benefits S just in case E is an MPA-benefit, or a plurality of MPA-benefits, for S.
GPH then implies that [Z’s taking pill A, Z’s taking pill B] benefits Z. He would have been worse off had neither event in this plurality occurred, and its only proper subpluralities are the singular events Z’s taking pill A and Z’s taking pill B. Each of those events is such that Z would have been better off had it not occurred.
The conclusion that [Z’s taking pill A, Z’s taking pill B] both harms and benefits Z is disastrous for GPH, since this account is intended to be an account of overall harm and benefit (see Feit 2015: 361; see also footnote 3 above). We take it to be an undisputable conceptual truth that if an event or a plurality of events is overall harmful for a person, then it is not also overall beneficial for this person. Hence, any plausible account of harm and benefit must satisfy the following adequacy condition:
Exclusion
No event or plurality of events is both overall harmful and overall beneficial for one and the same person.
By violating Exclusion, GPH is fatally flawed.
4 Feit’s QPH and why it fails
There is a twist, however. As we indicated above, it is not entirely correct that Feit accepts GPH. He argues that a certain “quantified” version of GPH, labeled ‘QPH’, is in fact more accurate (Feit 2015: 376–377). Let us say that a plurality E “MPA-harms S to degree n” (n > 0) just in case S would have been better off to degree n had none of the events in E occurred, and there is no proper subplurality of E such that S would have been better off to degree n had none of the events in it occurred. QPH can then be stated as follows:
Quantified plural harm (QPH)
A plurality of events E harms S to degree n if and only if E MPA-harms S to degree n, or is a plurality of MPA-harms, each of which MPA-harms S to degree n. Further, E harms S simpliciter if and only if there is some n such that E harms S to degree n.Footnote 8
QPH does not entail Agglomeration—on the contrary, QPH and Agglomeration are incompatible. Suppose that S would have been better off to degree 5 had event e not occurred, better off to degree 10 had event e* not occurred, and not better off at all had neither e nor e* occurred. There is then no n, such that [e, e*] MPA-harms S to degree n, or is a plurality of MPA-harms, each MPA-harming S to degree n. QPH hence implies that [e, e*] does not harm S, although each of e and e* does so.
However, QPH entails this weaker version of Agglomeration:
Weak agglomeration
If two pluralities E and E* harm S to the same degree, the plurality [E, E*] also harms S.
If we assume, in Painkillers, that abstaining from taking pill A and abstaining from taking pill B would have made Z better off to the same degree, QPH thus implies that [Z’s taking pill A, Z’s taking pill B] harms him. Supplementing QPH with the corresponding account of plural benefit, it is easy to verify that the resulting account also implies that this plurality benefits Z. Hence QPH, too, violates Exclusion.Footnote 9 In fact, QPH seems on the whole to fare even worse than GPH. It appears completely arbitrary to claim that two equally harmful pluralities always jointly make up a harmful plurality, but deny that two unequally harmful pluralities always do so.
5 Jedenheim Edling’s account and why it fails
Magnus Jedenheim Edling argues that Feit’s GPH yields dubious verdicts in preemption cases where the intuitively harmful events counterfactually depend on each other (2022: 1863–1865), as well as in some related cases (2022: 1869–1871). As a remedy, he suggests a slightly different account, called ‘New Plural Harm’ or ‘NPH’ (2022: 1866). In the same way that GPH builds on MPA, NPH builds on the following account:
Revised MPA
A plurality of events E harms S if and only if (i) S would have been better off had none of the events in E occurred, and (ii) no subplurality E* of E contains an event e such that S would have been better off had e but no other event in E* occurred.
Thus:
New Plural Harm (NPH)
A plurality of events E harms S if and only if E is a Revised MPA-harm, or a plurality of Revised MPA-harms, for S.Footnote 10
Like Feit, Jedenheim Edling intends his account as an account of overall harm (2022: 1854, fn. 1), and sees benefit as the converse of harm (2022: 1862).
Clearly, NPH entails both CCA and (unlike Revised MPA) Agglomeration. (In particular, note that when E is a singular event, Revised MPA’s first condition is satisfied if and only if E is a CCA-harm for S, and its second condition is satisfied trivially.) Since both Z’s taking pill A and Z’s taking pill B are CCA-harms for Z, NPH thus entails that the plurality [Z’s taking pill A, Z’s taking pill B] harms Z in Painkillers. But NPH, supplemented with the converse account of plural benefit, also implies that this plurality benefits Z. This is because this plurality is a Revised MPA-benefit for him. He would have been worse off if neither event in the plurality had occurred, and each event is such that if it had occurred without the other one, then he would not have been worse (but better) off. Hence, NPH violates Exclusion, and should accordingly be rejected.
6 A possible reply: denying that benefit is the converse of harm
A theoretical possibility would be for Feit and Jedenheim Edling to abandon their claim that harm and benefit should be given a parallel treatment. They could thus stick to their respective accounts of plural harm, and avoid violations of Exclusion by denying the claim—let us call it ‘Converse’—that benefit is the converse of harm.Footnote 11 Such a move would be problematic, however. Converse is widely accepted as well as intuitively plausible, and it provides a neat explanation of why Exclusion looks like an obvious conceptual truth. (See also Sect. 8.) Moreover, defenders of CCA about harm have at least two additional reasons to accept Converse. The first reason is that CCA about benefit has exactly the same degree of intuitive plausibility as CCA about harm. The claim that an event benefits a person just in case she would have been worse off in its absence seems neither more nor less plausible than the claim that an event harms her just in case she would have been better off in its absence. Rejecting CCA about benefit in order to avoid violations of Exclusion therefore appears arbitrary and ad hoc.
The second reason for adherents of CCA about harm to accept Converse is that CCA about harm and Exclusion together imply that an event benefits a person only if she would not have been better off had the event not occurred. This means that the correct account of benefit must be rather similar to CCA. Of course, the implication does not rule out that a person is benefitted by an event that leaves her equally well off as she would otherwise have been, or that she is neither harmed nor benefitted by an event that leaves her better off than she would otherwise have been. But if one or both of these possibilities are real, the defender of CCA about harm faces the task of explaining why a person cannot be harmed by an event that leaves her equally well off as she would otherwise have been, or why she cannot remain neither harmed nor benefitted by an event that leaves her worse off than she would otherwise have been. It is hard to think of plausible arguments for these asymmetries.Footnote 12
In addition, it is questionable whether denying Converse would get to the root of the problem. Letting ‘anti-harm’ denote the converse of harm, Feit’s and Jedenheim Edling’s accounts still imply that a plurality of events can be both harmful and anti-harmful for a person. This is implausible in itself, even if anti-harm does not exactly coincide with benefit. And things get worse, since these accounts also imply that it is impossible for a singular event to be both harmful and anti-harmful for a person. (We take it to be impossible for an event to leave a person both worse off and better off, overall, than she would otherwise have been.) It appears very strange that harmfulness and anti-harmfulness should be incompatible as regards singular events but compatible concerning pluralities of more than one event.
7 Capturing intuitions about plural and singular harm
We shall conclude this paper by providing, in this section and the next, some general reasons for thinking that CCA-friendly accounts of plural harm are unlikely to succeed. In the present section, we shall suggest that such accounts fail to accommodate certain central intuitions about plural and singular harm.
It may be thought that the lesson to learn from the failure of Feit’s and Jedenheim Edling’s accounts is that Agglomeration (or some weaker version thereof) is the culprit, and that proponents of the plural harm solution should stick to MPA or, perhaps, Revised MPA. We do not believe that this is the right conclusion, even though we find Feit’s and Jedenheim Edling’s reasons for preferring their respective accounts over MPA to be rather weak. In particular, it is far from obvious to us that the plurality of all three shootings harms Z in Three Shooters—after all, two shots would have been enough to kill Z, and MPA does have the plausible result that each two shot-plurality harms him. This is also the result yielded by Revised MPA. However, MPA and Revised MPA face more serious problems. One is that they classify what seem to be paradigmatic cases of harmful pluralities as harmless.Footnote 13 Consider:
Deadly Mixture
X and Y simultaneously, and independently of each other, use a syringe to inject a substance into Z’s body. X injects one substance, and Y injects another. Neither substance is toxic by itself, but their mixture is highly toxic. As a result, Z dies from poisoning.
In this case, [X’s injecting, Y’s injecting] seems clearly to qualify as a harmful plurality. Intuitively, Z is harmed by being injected with both substances—especially since neither injection would have affected Z’s well-being in the absence of the other one. Indeed, this is arguably more of a paradigm case of plural harm than are overdetermination and preemption cases. In Two Shooters, for example, each shooting would have negatively affected Z’s well-being (even) in the absence of the other one. In Deadly Mixture, however, [X’s injecting, Y’s injecting] does not harm Z according to MPA and Revised MPA. In the case of MPA, this is because each event in [X’s injecting, Y’s injecting] is a proper subplurality such that Z would have been better off had it not occurred. As regards Revised MPA, [X’s injecting, Y’s injecting] turns out harmless since it is a subplurality of itself, and contains an event such that Z would have been better off had this event but no other event in the subplurality occurred. Each of X’s injecting and Y’s injecting is such an event.
MPA and Revised MPA thus imply that whereas each of the two injections harms Z, their plurality does not. While it is plausible that each injection harms Z (in view of the occurrence of the other one), denying that they together harm Z seems contrary to the very idea of plural harm.
Of course, since MPA and Revised MPA imply that X’s injecting harms Z, and that Y’s injecting harms Z, MPA and Revised MPA imply that the two injections harm Z in a distributive sense of ‘harm’ (see Sect. 2). In other words, MPA and Revised MPA imply that the plurality [X’s injecting, Y’s injecting] is harmful in the sense that each singular event included in it is harmful. Clearly, however, this observation in no way accommodates the intuition that Deadly Mixture is a case of plural harm. Indeed, any two harms for a given person, even if entirely unrelated, make up a plurality that harms the person in the distributive sense. For instance, if Z is harmed by a mosquito bite as well as by an insulting remark, then the plurality of these events harms Z in the distributive sense, even assuming that the events have nothing whatsoever to do with each other. Such a case is very different from Deadly Mixture—again, it seems clear that the two injections (unlike the mosquito bite and the insulting remark) harm Z together. Thus, what needs to be accommodated is the claim that [X’s injecting, Y’s injecting] harms Z in the collective sense of ‘harms’—and the fact remains that MPA and Revised MPA are incompatible with that claim.
A further reason for pessimism about CCA with plural harm has to do with CCA’s implications about singular events in overdetermination and preemption cases—for example, X’s shooting in Two Shooters. As indicated in Sect. 2, while CCA problematically implies that X’s shooting does not harm Z, belonging to a plurality that harms Z might seem to be sufficiently close to itself harming Z to accommodate our intuitions about the case. On all CCA-friendly accounts of plural harm discussed here, however, an event can belong to a plurality that harms someone even if it is, intuitively, not at all involved in making trouble for her. Consider this case:
Late Shooter
X shoots and thereby kills Z. When Z is already dead, Y fires a shot, hitting Z’s body. If X had not shot Z, Y would still have shot, and would thereby have killed Z.
Intuitively, not only is Y’s action itself harmless to Z (although of course it would have harmed Z if X had not shot Z), it is not even involved in affecting Z’s well-being negatively. By the time of Y’s action and its effects, all work involved in harming Z is already completed and impossible to continue.Footnote 14 On all CCA-friendly accounts of plural harm discussed here, however, the plurality [X’s shooting, Y’s shooting] harms Z. Whether or not that implication is acceptable in isolation, it illustrates how far away, on these views, belonging to a plurality that harms someone is from itself harming her.Footnote 15 It is seriously doubtful, then, that placing Y’s act in a harmful plurality in cases like Two Shooters captures what needs to be captured. The same can be said about overdetermination and preemption cases more generally.
8 Counterfactuals and negatively affecting well-being
The points just made lead naturally to what we take to be the fundamental problem with both CCA and the various CCA-friendly accounts of plural harm that we have discussed. In our view, a very plausible idea about harm—and one that CCA and its main rivals can plausibly be seen as attempts to elucidate further—is that harming someone is negatively affecting her well-being.Footnote 16 Many well-known problems for CCA, including (but not limited to) those that concern preemption and overdetermination, illustrate that the view fails to do justice to this thought. A plausible diagnosis of this failure is that the notion of negatively affecting something cannot be captured in purely counterfactual terms. The following much-discussed preemption case provides a particularly clear illustration of this:
Dark Knight
Bobby Knight gets mad at a philosopher, Phil, in response to a perceived slight. So he chokes Phil. Luckily for Phil, Knight is in anger management. It’s taught him to better control his behavior. He choked Phil because he applied anger management techniques. If he hadn’t, he would have dismembered Phil. (Hanna 2016: 263; original version in Norcross 2005: 165–166)
It seems clear that Knight’s action harms Phil, contrary to what CCA yields. And it seems equally clear that Knight’s action also negatively affects Phil’s well-being. If harming is negatively affecting someone’s well-being, and if negatively affecting well-being cannot be analyzed counterfactually, it is unsurprising that these problems for CCA (which analyzes harming counterfactually) arise.
This diagnosis suggests that what CCA-friendly accounts of plural harm say about pluralities consisting of more than one event is bound to be implausible as well. For if harm is to be understood as negatively affecting someone’s well-being, then for some events to harm a person together is plausibly for them to negatively affect her well-being together. This idea about plural harm is intuitive in its own right and also helps explain why problems arise for CCA-friendly views of plural harm. For example, a plausible reason why the blackbird’s singing should not count as a member of a harmful plurality in Two Shooters is that it plays no role in negatively affecting the victim’s well-being level—it does so neither by itself nor together with any other events. In Deadly Mixture, by contrast, the two injections do seem to negatively impact the victim’s well-being level together—and this also appears to be a strong reason to think that they together harm him.
With respect to the problem that Painkillers poses for GPH and NPH, the idea that harming someone is connected to negatively affecting her well-being further supports the view that benefit is the converse of harm, since it is equally plausible that benefitting someone is positively affecting her well-being. This, in turn, explains why Exclusion seems obviously true, since an event or plurality of events cannot overall both negatively and positively influence someone’s well-being. In particular, we have a simple explanation of why the result that the plurality [Z’s taking pill A, Z’s taking pill B] both harms and benefits Z overall is unacceptable—it requires that the plurality both positively and negatively influences Z’s well-being overall, which cannot be the case.
Thus, if CCA’s problematic results are largely due to the fact that the notion of negatively affecting someone’s well-being cannot be captured in counterfactual terms, it is to be expected that all CCA-friendly accounts of plural harm—which likewise appeal solely to counterfactuals—will yield implausible results about when some events together harm a person.
Notes
For a critique of Feit’s approach that is independent of the concerns we shall raise here, see Johansson and Risberg (2019, Sect. 3).
Timmerman (2019: 244, fn. 6), too, endorses a CCA-friendly account of plural harm. Hanna (2016: 11–12), Immerman (2022: 46), McMahan (2002: 128), and Purves (2019: 2644, fn. 38) suggest that a successful modification of CCA needs to invoke plural harm. Petersson (2018) instead argues that CCA needs neither modification nor generalization, and that the plural harm approach is in tension with one of CCA’s main motivations—namely, that “making a difference to the worse for someone is essential to harming” (2018: 843).
CCA and all other accounts of harm to follow are accounts of overall harm, rather than pro tanto harm. In all of them, moreover, it is presupposed that the event or events in question actually occur.
This is evident from his discussion of a case similar to Three Shooters (Feit 2015: 375). In our view, MPA has a much more serious problem than this one; see Sect. 7.
We have reformulated GPH, attempting to make it more perspicuous.
An anonymous reviewer has suggested that GPH can be modified so as to avoid the conclusion that [Z’s taking pill A, Z’s taking pill B] harms Z in Painkillers. More precisely, the reviewer suggests the following modification:
Revised GPH: A plurality of events E harms S if and only if (i) E is an MPA-harm, or a plurality of MPA-harms, for S, and (ii) S would have been better off had no event in E occurred.
We believe, however, that Feit should resist this move. Consider the following case:
Three Injectors: Z is about to die from a snake bite. X, Y, and U simultaneously, and independently of each other, inject Z with an antidote. This antidote is such that one shot cures you, while two shots or more kill you. Hence, Z dies, and he would have survived just in case he had received exactly one shot.
In this case, GPH and Revised GPH imply that each pair of injections, taken as a plurality, harms Z. GPH also implies that the plurality of all three injections harms him. Revised GPH, on the other hand, yields the result that this plurality does not harm Z. (He would not have been better off had he received no shot.) As we saw, Feit’s motivation for rejecting MPA in favor of the more complicated GPH is that he takes the plurality of all the relevant events to be harmful in cases like Three Shooters. And it would be very implausible, we think, to claim that the plurality of all three shootings is harmful in Three Shooters, but deny that the plurality of all three injections is harmful in the structurally similar Three Injectors. Hence, Feit and other potential adherents of GPH should not be attracted by Revised GPH.
The reviewer also suggests that the most plausible verdict in Painkillers is that taking both pills harms Z while taking at least one pill benefits him. Whether or not this verdict is plausible, it requires a significant departure from the framework favored by adherents of the plural harm approach, since Z’s taking at least one pill is not plausibly a concrete event but rather (something like) an abstract state of affairs. And if such non-events can be harmful we do not need to invoke plural harm to handle Two Shooters, since we can simply say that what harms Z is being shot by at least one of X and Y. Clearly, this undercuts the motivation for the plural harm approach.
In this context, the idea that benefit is the “converse” of harm can be clarified along the following lines. Let T be a sentence stating the analysans of the correct analysis of harm (e.g., ‘S would have been better off if e had not occurred’), and let T* be a sentence that differs from T only in that the axiological terms in T are replaced by ones with the opposite “valence” (e.g., ‘S would have been worse off if e had not occurred’). Then benefit is the converse of harm if and only if T* states the analysans of the correct analysis of benefit. While this suggestion would have to be modified in a discussion of views of harm that are not value-based (such as rights-based ones), it will suffice for present purposes.
Again, we have reformulated Feit’s account.
Feit (2015: 377–378) briefly suggests that a “fully adequate account [of harm] should make harm relative to time” and “take E harms S to degree n at [time] t to be the basic unit of analysis.” See also Jedenheim Edling (2022: 1861, fn. 12). Clearly, this does not solve the problem, since we can simply stipulate that abstaining from taking pill A and abstaining from taking pill B would have made Z better off to the same degree at the same time.
We have reformulated NPH.
Comments by an anonymous reviewer prompted us to discuss this possibility. For a clarification of Converse, see footnote 7.
It would, of course, be logically possible to accept Converse for single-event harm but deny it for plural harm. But this option seems too implausible to be worth serious consideration. The same goes for the possibility of accepting the existence of plural harm but denying the existence of plural benefit.
We sidestep here special issues to do with posthumous harm. Even if there is posthumous harm, there are many ways to fill out the details of the case (e.g., stipulating that Y’s shooting does not frustrate any of Z’s desires) that would leave our main point unaffected.
In the case of Revised MPA and NPH, even more striking illustrations are available. For example, suppose that X shoots Z to death at t, and that Z’s corpse is then frozen at -30 degrees Celsius. At a later time t*, Y raises the temperature of Z’s corpse to -29 degrees. Suppose that Z would have had no positive or negative well-being level between t and t* regardless of what X and Y had done, but that if neither X’s shooting nor Y’s action had occurred, then Z would have been better off (by becoming well off after t*). Clearly, neither X’s nor Y’s action is such that if it had occurred without the other one, Z would have been better off. In particular, if Y’s but not X’s action had occurred, Z would still be dead by t*. (In the nearest possible world in which Y’s but not X’s action occurs, something other than X’s action kills Z before t*.) Both Revised MPA and NPH thus imply that [X’s shooting, Y’s raising the temperature of Z’s corpse to -29 degrees] harms Z. (Assuming, realistically, that Y’s action counterfactually depends on X’s, MPA and GPH lack this implication.) Whether or not this implication is acceptable in isolation (although we think it is not), it is obvious that Y’s action is very far away from itself harming Z.
For elaboration and defense of this idea, see Johansson and Risberg (forthcoming). This idea takes well-being—rather than, for instance, rights, interests, or physical health—to be the “currency” of harm (see, e.g., Gardner 2021; Tadros 2014). With appropriate adjustments, however, our main claims in this section can equally well be made from the perspective of rival views about the currency of harm. Our focus here is on negatively affecting something, not on well-being.
References
Bradley, B. (2009). Well-being and death. Oxford University Press.
Feit, N. (2015). Plural harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 361–388. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12033.
Feit, N. (2016). Comparative harm, creation and death. Utilitas, 28(2), 136–163. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0953820815000308.
Feit, N. (2022). How harms can be better than benefits: Reply to Carlson, Johansson, and Risberg. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 100(3), 628–633. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2021.1951781.
Gardner, M. (2021). What is harming?. In J. McMahan, et al. (Eds.), Principles and persons: The legacy of Derek Parfit (pp. 381–395). Oxford University Press.
Hanna, N. (2016). Harm: omission, preemption, freedom. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(2), 251–273. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12244.
Immerman, D. (2022). The worse than nothing account of harm and the preemption problem. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 19(1), 25–48. https://doi.org/10.1163/17455243-20213139.
Jedenheim Edling, M. (2022). A new principle of plural harm. Philosophical Studies, 179(6), 1853–1872. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01735-9.
Johansson, J., & Risberg, O. (2019). The preemption problem. Philosophical Studies, 176(2), 351–365. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-1019-x.
Johansson, J., & Risberg, O. (forthcoming). A simple analysis of harm. Ergo.
McMahan, J. (2002). The ethics of killing: Problems at the margins of life. Oxford University Press.
Norcross, A. (2005). Harming in context. Philosophical Studies, 123(1&2), 149–173. https://doi.org/10.1007/sI1098-004-5220-3.
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford University Press.
Petersson, B. (2018). Over-determined harms and harmless pluralities. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21(4), 841–850. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-018-9913-7.
Purves, D. (2019). Harming as making worse off. Philosophical Studies, 176(10), 2629–2656. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1144-1.
Tadros, V. (2014). What might have been. In J. Oberdiek (Ed.), Philosophical foundations of the law of torts (pp. 171–192). Oxford University Press.
Timmerman, T. (2019). A dilemma for Epicureanism. Philosophical Studies, 176(1), 241–257. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-1014-2.
Acknowledgements
Three anonymous reviewers for this journal provided very valuable comments on earlier versions of this article. For helpful discussion, we are also grateful to Neil Feit, Magnus Jedenheim Edling, Eli Pitcovski, and the audience at a digital seminar at Tel Hai Academic College, Israel, in December 2021. Further, we wish to acknowledge financial support from Vetenskapsrådet, Grants 2018 − 01361 and 2020 − 01955, and from Riksbankens Jubileumsfond, Grant P21-0462.
Funding
Open access funding provided by Uppsala University.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher’s note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
About this article
Cite this article
Carlson, E., Johansson, J. & Risberg, O. Plural harm: plural problems. Philos Stud 180, 553–565 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01913-3
Received:
Revised:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01913-3