Abstract
A good chunk of the recent discussion of hypocrisy concerned the hypocritical “moral address” where, in the simplest case, a person criticises another for \(\phi \)-ing having engaged in \(\phi \)-ing himself, and where the critic’s reasons are overtly moral. The debate has conceptual and normative sides to it. We ask both what hypocrisy is, and why it is wrong. In this paper I focus on the conceptual explication of hypocrisy by examining the pragmatic features of the situation where accusations of hypocrisy are made. After rejecting several extant views, I defend the idea that moral criticisms are best understood as moves in an agonistic or hostile conversation, and that charges of hypocrisy are attempts to prevent the hypocrite from gaining an upper hand in a situation of conflict. I finish by linking this idea to frame-theoretic analysis and evolutionary psychology.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
Subjunctive hypocrisy: Piovarchy (2020:10–11).
This brings me to another disclaimer, that criticisms not couched in moral terms are outside the scope of our discussion. This includes, e.g., the emotionally charged, angry complaints of the kind sketched in Wolf (2011).
See, e.g., Wallace (2010), Rossi (2021), and every writer in the debate cited here, with the possible exception of Dover (2019a) discussed below. But whatever the consensus in the current debate over blame and hypocrisy, might we not say generally that hypocrisy is often a salutary phenomenon, so far as it serves a useful social purpose? This, for example, is a view espoused in Mandeville (1924). Yet even Mandeville assumes at the outset that hypocrisy (or at least some of its forms) is in itself odious, although we may have to tolerate it for the sake of public utility. See, e.g., Douglass (2022:469).
Well, can’t there be hypocritical blame that has never been expressed verbally? Certainly. But I think it should be understood as a defect of character. It is a principally different form of hypocrisy to be given a different treatment. For example, a silent hypocrite wouldn’t be guilty of deceiving others. He should instead be criticised for his own self-deception. See Berkovski (2022) for a discussion of public and silent hypocrisies and their links to self-deception. In any event, as mentioned earlier, this form of hypocrisy is outside the purview of this paper. The present task is to reconstruct the dynamics of a verbal interaction where hypocrisy is a driving force.
See Tonhauser et al. (2013:81).
See Simons (2006:358).
Since there is no presumption that \(M\) is conveyed pragmatically at all, it would be misleading to apply the usual tests of conversational implicature, like cancellabiliy or reinforceability. These tests are designed to distinguish implicature from other kinds of non-at-issue content. But if \(M\) is not such a content in the first place, it may pass these tests trivially.
A version of this view is in Shoemaker and Vargas (2021). I discuss it in more detail elsewhere. The terminology of “cue” is from Maynard Smith and Harper (2003) where it is contrasted with “signals”. This contrast is loosely analogous to the one between meaning\(_{\text {N}}\) and meaning\(_{\text {NN}}\) of Grice (1957).
Special conditions for the cue to become pragmatic: Grice (1989:100–104).
See, e.g., Shafer-Landau (2003:15) for a careful formulation of moral realism.
This connects to the issue of the emotional component of Scanlon’s blame. See Wolf (2011).
Compare a related discussion in Portner (2016:606).
The precedent here is, of course, the original discussion in Austin (1975:16).
Throughout I assume a traditional view of assertion, rather than a revisionist one like in Williamson (2000:249ff). Note too that the revisionist is likely to dispute the felicity of Cohen’s puzzle (6) on a combination of moral and epistemic grounds.
Curiously, Isserow and Klein (2017:199n16) mention the possibility of exactly this kind of explanation, but declare themselves unperturbed—wrongly, in my view.
Could a known hypocrite plausibly issue a moral criticism? This interesting possibility will be addressed shortly. Secondly, what of a criticism made in private where \(A\) criticises \(B\) in a one-on-one interaction? Again, so far as \(A\)’s judgement is valuable to \(B\), the latter has an interest in protecting \(A\)’s positive judgement of himself. More generally, we may appeal to the notion of “face” and say that also in dyadic interactions people protect their face and project a positive image of themselves (Brown and Levinson 1987). Moral criticisms damage the criticised person’s face.
See Crisp and Cowton (1994:347).
Standard pragmatic account: Stalnaker (2014).
Accommodation: Stalnaker (2014:6, 47ff).
See the instructive remarks in Stalnaker (2014:75ff).
See, e.g., the concessions in Dover (2019a:41).
Note that the constructive model also lacks an explanation why moral criticisms can regularly appear in “friendly” frames—why, in other words, they should not trigger agonistic transformation. Dover acknowledges this deficiency in (2019a:43), but offers no positive proposal.
Goffman’s distinctions are refined in Levinson (1988).
The “natural setting” of moral judgement: Haidt (2001:820).
Judges may also praise, but as DeScioli and Kurzban note, condemnation prevails.
References
Alston, W. P. (2000). Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Ithaca: Cornell Universty Press.
Austin, J. L. (1975). How to Do Things with Words. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2nd edn. Edited by J. O. Urmson and M. Sbisà.
Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Berkovski, Y. S. (2022). Mandeville on self-liking, morality, and hypocrisy. Intellectual History Review, 32(1), 157–178.
Brown, P., & Levinson, S. C. (1987). Politeness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chafe, W. L. (1994). Discourse, Consciousness, and Time. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Cohen, G. A. (2013a). Casting the first stone. In Cohen (2013).
Cohen, G. A. (2013c). Ways of silencing critics. In Cohen (2013).
Cohen, G. A. (2013). Finding Oneself in the Other. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Crisp, R., & Cowton, C. (1994). Hypocrisy and moral seriousness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31(4), 343–349.
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2009). Mysteries of morality. Cognition, 119, 281–299.
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2013). A solution to the mysteries of morality. Psychological Bulletin, 139(2), 477–496.
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2018). Morality is for choosing sides. In K. Gray & J. Graham (Eds.), Atlas of Moral Psychology. New York: Guilford Press.
Douglass, R. (2022). Bernard Mandeville on the use and abuse of hypocrisy. Political Studies, 70(2), 465–482.
Dover, D. (2019). Criticism as conversation. Philosophical Perspectives, 33, 26–61.
Dover, D. (2019). The walk and the talk. Philosophical Review, 128(4), 387–422.
Dworkin, G. (2000). Morally speaking. In E. Ullmann-Margalit (Ed.), Reasoning Practically. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.
Fillmore, C. J. (1975). Frame semantics and the nature of language. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 280(1), 20–32.
Fillmore, C. J. (1985). Frames and the semantics of understanding. Quaderni di Semantica, 6(2), 222–254.
Fritz, K. G., & Miller, D. (2018). Hypocrisy and the standing to blame. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 118–139.
Goffman, E. (1974). Frame Analysis. New York: Harper & Row.
Goffman, E. (1981). Forms of Talk. Philadelphia: Univerity of Pennsylvania Press.
Grice, H. P. (1989). Utterer’s meaning and intentions. In Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press.
Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66(3), 377–388.
Gumperz, J. J. (1982). Discourse Strategies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814–834.
Isserow, J., & Klein, C. (2017). Hypocrisy and moral authority. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 12(2).
Kurzban, R. (2010). Why Everyone (Else) is a Hypocrite: Evolution and the Modular Mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Langacker, R. W. (2012). Interactive cognition: Toward a unified account of structure, processing, and discourse. International Journal of Cognitive Linguistics, 3(2), 95–125.
Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Levinson, S. C. (1988). Putting linguistics on a proper footing. In P. Drew & A. Wootton (Eds.), Erving Goffman: Exploring the Interaction Order. Polity PressPolity PressPolity PressPolity Press.
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2020). Why the moral equality account of the hypocrite’s lack of standing to blame fails. Analysis, 80(4), 666–674.
Mandeville, B. (1924). The Fable of the Bees, volume 1. Clarendon Press. Edited by F. B. Kaye.
Maynard Smith, J., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal Signals. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.
Piovarchy, A. (2020). Situationism, subjunctive hypocrisy and standing to blame. Inquiry. Forthcoming.
Portner, P. (2016). Imperatives. In M. Aloni & P. Dekker (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Formal Semantics (pp. 593–628). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Potts, C. (2015). Presupposition and implicature. In S. Lappin & C. Fox (Eds.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory (pp. 168–202). Hoboken: Wiley Blackwell.
Riedener, S. (2019). The standing to blame, or Why moral disapproval is what it is. Dialectica, 73(1–2), 183–210.
Rossi, B. (2018). The commitment account of hypocrisy. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21, 553–567.
Rossi, B. (2021). Hypocrisy is vicious, value-expressing inconsistency. Journal of Ethics, 25, 57–80.
Scanlon, T. M. (2008). Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning. Blame: Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA and London.
Searle, J. R., & Vanderveken, D. (1985). Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Shklar, J. N. (1979). Let us not be hypocritical. Daedalus, 108(3), 1–25.
Shoemaker, D., & Vargas, M. (2021). Moral torch fishing: A signaling theory of blame. Noûs, 55(3), 581–602.
Simons, M. (2006). Foundational issues in presupposition. Philosophy. Compass, 1(4), 357–372.
Stalnaker, R. C. (2014). Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Szabados, B. (1979). Hypocrisy. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 9(2), 195–210.
Todd, P. (2019). A unified account of the moral standing to blame. Noûs, 53(2), 347–374.
Tonhauser, J., Beaver, D., Roberts, C., & Simons, M. (2013). Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language, 89(1), 66–109.
Trollope, A. (1985). Orley Farm. Oxford Univeristy Press. Edited by D. Skilton.
von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The King of France is back! In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and Beyond. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.
Wallace, R. J. (2010). Hypocrisy, moral address, and the equal standing of persons. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(4), 307–341.
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wolf, S. (2011). Blame, Italian style. In R. J. Wallace, R. Kumar, & S. Freeman (Eds.), Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T.M. Scanlon. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.
Acknowledgements
I’m grateful to an anonymous referee for useful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Berkovski, Y.S. Moral criticism, hypocrisy, and pragmatics. Philos Stud 180, 1–26 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01862-x
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01862-x
Keywords
- Hypocrisy
- Blame
- Pragmatics