Skip to main content
Log in

Against (modified) buffer cases

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I defend the principle of alternative possibilities (PAP) against what are sometimes known as buffer cases, which are supposed by some to be counterexamples to the principle. I develop an existing problem with the claim that standard buffer cases are counterexamples to PAP, before responding to a recent attempt by Michael McKenna (2018) to modify the cases in a way that circumvents this problem. While McKenna’s strategy does avoid the problem, I argue that it faces a different difficulty. I conclude that (modified) buffer cases pose no threat to PAP.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and material

Not applicable.

Code availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. Robert Kane (1985: 51) first suggested this dilemma. Versions of it have subsequently been developed and defended by Ginet (1996), Widerker (1995), and Wyma (1997), among several others.

  2. Hunt (2000) and (2005) and Hunt and Shabo (2013) also defend buffer cases. For Pereboom's earlier discussions of buffer cases, see Pereboom (2000, 2001, 2005, 2012).

  3. But see Franklin (2011), Ginet (2002), and Palmer (2011) and (2013) for attempts to resist it. See Capes (2016) for some potential downsides to the sort of position defended by Franklin, Ginet, and Palmer.

  4. I owe this sort of example to Philip Swenson, who, if memory serves, suggested something like it in conversation once. McKenna (2018: 3122) discusses a similar example, though he puts it to a slightly different use.

  5. In Capes (2016), I develop some other difficulties with Pereboom’s argument.

  6. An anonymous referee suggested that, in this paragraph, I have begged the question against the Frankfurt-defender. But I see things differently. Frankfurt cases like Tax Cut 2 are supposed to provide us with cases in which the agent lacks a robust alternative but is blameworthy for what she does nonetheless. But why should we accept the claim that the agent in such cases is blameworthy? It might be said that that claim is just intuitively obvious. But that’s what I deny. I claim that, when we focus carefully on the features of the case as described, it’s not intuitively obvious that the agent is blameworthy, which means that we need further reason to suppose that she is blameworthy, if the argument against PAP based on Tax Cut 2 is going to succeed. My claim, then, is that the mere assertion that the agent in a case like Tax Cut 2 is blameworthy is not intuitively obvious and thus requires further defense. By itself, that claim doesn’t beg the question; it is simply to insist that a premise in the argument against PAP needs further support. Note, moreover, that I do go on to argue below for the claim that incompatibilists at least should judge Jones not to be blameworthy for his action in Tax Cut 2.

  7. Elzein (2017) makes a similar point.

  8. A referee worries that the strong notion of control at play in my argument here, which involves the possibility of the agent actively bringing about an alternative possibility, will have the seemingly implausible result that we often don’t have the sort of control or free will required for moral responsibility, even when it seems like we do. While this is an issue I take seriously, it would take us too far afield to address it here. Suffice it to say that I think the result in question much less implausible than it might initially seem. Substantiating that claim, though, is the task for another article.

References

  • Capes, J. (2016). Blameworthiness and buffered alternatives. American Philosophical Quarterly, 53, 270–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elzein, N. (2017). Frankfurt-style counterexamples and the importance of alternative Possibilities. Acta Analytica, 32, 169–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, C. E. (2011). Neo-Frankfurtians and buffer cases: The new challenge to the principle of alternative possibilities. Philosophical Studies, 152, 189–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1996). In defense of the principle of alternative possibilities: Why I don’t find Frankfurt’s argument convincing. Philosophical Perspectives, 10, 403–417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (2002). Review of Living without free will. Journal of Ethics, 6, 305–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. (2000). Moral responsibility and unavoidable action. Philosophical Studies, 97, 195–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. (2005). Moral responsibility and buffered alternatives. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 126–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D., & Shabo, S. (2013). Frankfurt cases and the (in)significance of timing. Philosophical Studies, 164, 599–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1985). Free will and values. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2018). A critical assessment of Pereboom’s Frankfurt-style example. Philosophical Studies, 175, 3117–3129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, D. (2011). Pereboom on the Frankfurt cases. Philosophical Studies, 153, 261–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, D. (2013). The timing objection to the Frankfurt cases. Erkenntnis, 78, 1011–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2000). Alternate possibilities and causal histories. Philosophical Perspectives, 14, 119–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2005). Defending hard incompatibilism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 228–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2012). Frankfurt examples, derivative responsibility, and the timing objection. Philosophical Issues, 22, 298–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2014). Free will, agency, and meaning in life. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Widerker, D. (1995). Libertarianism and Frankfurt’s attack on the principle of alternative possibilities. Philosophical Review, 104, 247–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wyma, K. (1997). Moral responsibility and leeway for action. American Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 57–70.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to an anonymous referee for this journal for helpful feedback.

Funding

Not applicable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justin A. Capes.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

Not applicable.

Ethical approval

Not applicable.

Consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Capes, J.A. Against (modified) buffer cases. Philos Stud 179, 711–723 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01678-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01678-1

Keywords

Navigation