Skip to main content
Log in

Moral responsibility and manipulation: on a novel argument against historicism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Taylor Cyr offers a novel argument against, as he puts it, “all versions of historicism” about direct moral responsibility (Philos Stud. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01315-y, 2019). The argument features constitutive luck and a comparison of manipulated agents and young agents performing the first actions for which they are morally responsible. Here it is argued that Cyr’s argument misses its mark. Alfred Mele’s historicism is highlighted.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. My use of “value” is pretty undemanding. In Mele (1995), I offer glosses on the verb and the noun. As I understand valuing there, “S at least thinly values X at a time if and only if at that time S both has a positive motivational attitude toward X and believes X to be good” (p. 116). When values are understood as psychological states, I take them to have both of these dimensions by definition. This account of thinly valuing and the corresponding thin account of values are not meant to be contributions to the theories of valuing and values; their purpose was to make my meaning clear. I use “value” in the same way here.

  2. Frankfurt would not resist the assertion that Betty’s desire to kill George is “well integrated into [her] general psychic condition.” Betty, in this story, is an agent of the sort Frankfurt has in mind in the following passage: “A manipulator may succeed, through his interventions, in providing a person not merely with particular feelings and thoughts but with a new character. That person is then morally responsible for the choices and the conduct to which having this character leads” (2002, p. 28).

  3. A potential source of confusion should be identified. Cyr’s mention of mental health here echoes an element of an alleged sufficient condition for free action offered in Mele (2006) and quoted by Cyr (2019, p. 4). Cyr mistakenly treats this condition as though it were also offered as a necessary condition for free action (see the sentence in Cyr (2019) that immediately follows the quoted condition and the first sentence of his note 4). Neither Chuck nor post-manipulation Betty seems mentally healthy. But given that I do not make mental health a necessary condition for directly free action nor for directly morally responsible action, that is not a problem for me.

  4. Suppose that, in my original story about Beth, the manipulators implanted in her (in addition to the Ann-like values) a belief that a life organized around hard philosophical work would make her happiest, which belief played a significant role in producing Beth’s endorsement of her new values the next morning. A referee asked for a comparison of this belief with a similar belief that Beth has a year later—the belief that a life organized around hard philosophical work makes her happiest. Notice that Beth acquired the implanted belief in a way that bypasses her capacities for control over her mental life, whereas the latter belief, a year later, is acquired in an experience-based way that does not bypass those capacities.

  5. “Instant agents” is David Zimmerman’s term for agents “who spring full-blown into existence…. Mele’s ‘Athena’ and Davidson’s ‘swampman’ are vivid examples” (1999, p. 252). For Athena and swampman, see Mele (1995, pp. 172–73) and Davidson (1987). I return to instant agents in various places, including, most recently, Mele (2019).

  6. For comments on a draft of this article, I am grateful to Taylor Cyr and an anonymous referee.

References

  • Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled virtue. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyr, T. (2019). Manipulation and constitutive luck. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01315-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60, 441–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1984). Elbow room. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1988). The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (2002). Reply to John Martin Fischer. In S. Buss & L. Overton (Eds.), Contours of agency. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (1995). Autonomous agents. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2009a). Moral responsibility and agents’ histories. Philosophical Studies, 142, 161–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2009b). Moral responsibility and history revisited. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12, 463–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2016). Moral responsibility: Radical reversals and original designs. Journal of Ethics, 20, 69–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2019). Manipulated agents. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, D. (1999). Born yesterday: Personal autonomy for agents without a past. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23, 236–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfred R. Mele.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mele, A.R. Moral responsibility and manipulation: on a novel argument against historicism. Philos Stud 177, 3143–3154 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01363-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01363-4

Keywords

Navigation