Advertisement

Manipulation and constitutive luck

  • Taylor W. CyrEmail author
Article

Abstract

I argue that considerations pertaining to constitutive luck undermine historicism—the view that an agent’s history can determine whether or not she is morally responsible. The main way that historicists have motivated their view is by appealing to certain cases of manipulation. I argue, however, that since agents can be morally responsible for performing some actions from characters with respect to which they are entirely constitutively lucky, and since there is no relevant difference between these agents and agents who have been manipulated into acting from a character bestowed upon them by their manipulators, we should give up historicism. After presenting this argument and defending it against some potential objections, I briefly criticize the standard structuralist alternative and propose a new structuralist position that is shaped by reflection on constitutive luck.

Keywords

Constitutive luck Historicism Manipulation Moral responsibility Structuralism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

For comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I am grateful to John Fischer and Michael Nelson; the members of the Agency Workshop at the University of California, Riverside, especially Zac Bachman, Dave Beglin, Andrew Law, Meredith McFadden, Jonah Nagashima, and Debbie Nelson; my commentator at the 2017 Pacific APA in Seattle, Ben Matheson; the audience at that APA, especially Craig Agule, Garrett Pendergraft, Michael Robinson, Philip Swenson, and Neal Tognazzini; and to an anonymous reviewer for this journal. I am also grateful to Al Mele for discussion of the main argument of this paper.

References

  1. Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Cyr, T. (2019). Moral responsibility, luck, and compatibilism. Erkenntnis, 84, 193–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Cyr, T. (Manuscript). Manipulation arguments and libertarian accounts of free will.Google Scholar
  4. Fischer, J. M. (2012). Responsibility and autonomy: The problem of mission creep. Philosophical Issues, 22, 165–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Frankfurt, H. (1988). The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. McKenna, M. (2004). Responsibility and globally manipulated agents. Philosophical Topics, 32, 169–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. McKenna, M. (2012). Moral responsibility, manipulation arguments, and history: Assessing the resilience of nonhistorical compatibilism. Journal of Ethics, 16, 145–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. McKenna, M. (2016). A Modest Historical Theory of Moral Responsibility. Journal of Ethics, 20, 83–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Mele, A. (1995). Autonomous agents: From self-control to autonomy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Nagel, T. (1979). Moral luck. In Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Pereboom, D. (2014). Free will, agency, and meaning in life. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Watson, G. (2004). Agency and answerability: Selected essays. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Samford UniversityBirminghamUSA

Personalised recommendations