Skip to main content
Log in

Causation in terms of production

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we analyse actual causation in terms of production. The latter concept is made precise by a strengthened Ramsey Test semantics of conditionals: \(A \gg C\) iff, after suspending judgement about A and C, C is believed in the course of assuming A. This test allows us to (epistemically) verify or falsify that an event brings about another event. Complementing the concept of production by a weak condition of difference-making gives rise to a full-fledged analysis of causation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Gärdenfors (1986) has proven a triviality theorem concerning the Ramsey Test, after a conditional logic was developed on the basis of this test in Gärdenfors (1979). Recently, however, there have been various, apparently successful attempts at defending the Ramsey Test in light of this result [see, e.g., Bradley (2007)]. We show that our strengthened Ramsey Test does not imply triviality in Andreas and Günther (2018a). The following section draws on this paper, where the conditional \(\gg \) has been defined for the first time.

  2. In the Treatise, Hume (1739/1978, p. 170, our emphasis) defines: “A cause is an object precedent and contiguous to another, and so united with it, that the idea of the one determines the mind to form the idea of the other”. In more modern terms, if an event C precedes another E (and is contiguous), Hume calls C a cause of E iff C is an epistemic reason for E. Observe that the notion of causation is relative to a ‘mind’.

  3. A diagram of a model \({\mathcal {A}}\) is the set of all closed literals (in a given language) that are true in \({\mathcal {A}}\). The notion of a first order diagram has a clear analogue for propositional languages. In the case of propositional logic, a diagram contains for any propositional constant A, either A or \(\lnot A\). Such a diagram represents a valuation of a language of propositional logic.

  4. Many thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing our attention to scenarios of the present type.

  5. Condition (C4) is inspired by Rott (1986). Recently, a conceptually similar condition has been used by Beckers and Vennekens (2017, 2018) in an analysis of actual causation.

  6. In Andreas and Günther (2018b), we defined the strengthened Ramsey Test in the framework of causal models by Halpern and Pearl (2005). Thereby, we put forth a variant of the present analysis of actual causation in terms of causal models. The analysis there is not reductive since structural equations of a causal model are presumed to encode primitive causal relations.

References

  • Alchourrón, M. A., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction functions and their associated revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreas, H., & Günther, M. (2018a). On the Ramsey Test analysis of ‘Because’. Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0006-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreas, H., & Günther, M. (2018b). A Ramsey Test analysis of causation for causal models. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy074.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreas, H. (2019). Explanatory conditionals. Philosophy of Science, 86(5).

  • Beckers, S., & Vennekens, J. (2017). The transitivity and asymmetry of actual causation. Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy, 4, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beckers, S., & Vennekens, J. (2018). A principled approach to defining actual causation. Synthese, 195(2), 835–862.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R. (2007). A defence of the ramsey test. Mind, 116(461), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1979). Conditionals and changes of belief. In I. Niiniluoto, R. Tuomela, (Eds.), The logic and epistemology of scientific change. Volume 30 of Acta philosophica fennica (pp. 381–404). Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1986). Belief revisions and the ramsey test for conditionals. The Philosophical Review, 95(1), 81–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2007). Structural equations and causation. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 109–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In John Collins, Ned Hall, & Laurie Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J . Y., & Pearl, J. (2005). Causes and explanations: A structural-model approach. Part I: Causes. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 56(4), 843–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1999). A textbook of belief dynamics. Theory change and database updating. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1992). In defense of the ramsey test. Journal of Philosophy, 89(10), 522–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs. Journal of Philosophy, 98(6), 273–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739/1978). A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70(17), 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Postscripts to “causation”. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 172–213). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A., & Hall, N. (2013). A user’s guide. Causation: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1929/1990). General propositions and causality. In Philosophical papers (pp. 145–163).

  • Rott, H. (1986). Ifs, though, and because. Erkenntnis, 25(3), 345–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2005). Causes as difference-makers. Philosophical Studies, 123(1), 71–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2006). Causation: An alternative. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(1), 93–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (American philosophical quarterly monograph series) (Vol. 2, pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Hannes Leitgeb and Andrew Irvine for very valuable advice on earlier versions of the paper. Special thanks are also due to Hans Rott and Paul Bartha for very helpful comments on presentations of the paper. Finally, we are indebted to the anonymous referees for Philosophical Studies. Their comments greatly helped us improve the paper. This research has been supported, in part, by the Graduate School of Systemic Neurosciences.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario Günther.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andreas, H., Günther, M. Causation in terms of production. Philos Stud 177, 1565–1591 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01275-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01275-3

Keywords

Navigation