A liberal theory of externalities?

Article
  • 33 Downloads

Abstract

Unlike exploitative exchanges, exchanges featuring externalities have never seemed to pose particular problems to liberal theories of justice. State interference with exchanges featuring externalities seems permissible, like it is for coercive or deceptive exchanges. This is because exchanges featuring negative externalities seem to be clear cases of the two exchanging parties harming a third one via the exchange—and thus of conduct violating the harm principle. This essay aims to put this idea into question. I will argue that exchanges featuring negative externalities are not unjust in this straightforward way, i.e. because they would constitute an instance of wrongfully causing or risking a bodily or material harm. In fact, unless we are subscribing to particularly demanding variants of liberalism—e.g. perfectionist liberalism—or unless we are exclusively focusing on borderline cases of externalities—i.e. of effects of exchanges hardly to be called externalities—there is no liberal theory of how exchanges featuring externalities are unjust.

Keywords

Externalities Liberalism Exchanges Harm principle Justice 

References

  1. Anderson, E. (1993). Value in ethics and economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Child, J. W. (1994). Can libertarianism sustain a fraud standard? Ethics, 104(4), 722–738.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Coase, R. (1960). The Problem of Social Cost. Journal of Law and Economics, 3, 1–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cohen, G. A. (1988). History, labour and freedom: Themes from Marx. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  5. Dancy, J. (2000). Practical reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Duff, R. A. (1990). ‘Can I help you?’ accessorial liability and the intention to assist. Legal Studies, 10(2), 165–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Duff, R. A. (2007). Answering for crime: Responsibility and liability in the criminal law. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
  8. Duff, R. A., & Marshall, S. E. (2015). ‘Abstract endangerment’, two harm principles, and two routes to criminalisation. Bergen Journal of Criminal Law and Criminal Justice, 3(2), 131–161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Dworkin, R. (1986). Law’s empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Feinberg, J. (1984). Harm to others: The moral limits of the criminal law (Vol. 1). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Feinberg, J. (1988). Harmless wrongdoing: The moral limits of the criminal law (Vol. 4). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, A. M. (1985). Causation in the law (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Honoré, A. M. (2010). Causation in the Law. In: Zalta, Edward N (Eds.) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2010 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/causation-law/.
  14. Husak, D. (2007). Overcriminalization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Kadish, S. H. (1985). Complicity, cause and blame. California Law Review, 73(2), 329–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kagan, S. (2011). Do I make a difference? Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39(2), 105–141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Lichtenberg, J. (2010). Negative duties, positive duties, and the ‘new harms’. Ethics, 120, 557–578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Mankiw, N. G. (2004). Principles of economics (3rd ed.). Mason, Ohio: Thomson/South-Western.Google Scholar
  19. Mill, J. S. [1859] (1991a). On liberty. In Gray, J. (Ed.), On liberty and other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Mill, J. S. [1861] (1991b). Utilitarianism. In Gray, J. (Ed.) On liberty and other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Moore, M. S. (2007). Causing, aiding, and the superfluity of accomplice liability. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 156(2), 395–452.Google Scholar
  22. Nozick, R. (1977). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  23. Pindyck, R. S., & Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (2013). Microeconomics (8th ed.). Boston: Pearson.Google Scholar
  24. Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  25. Skorupski, J. (2010). The domain of reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Steiner, H. (1984). A liberal theory of exploitation. Ethics, 94(2), 225–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Thomson, J. J. (1986). Rights, restitution, and risk. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Varian, H. R. (2006). Intermediate microeconomics (7th ed.). New York and London: W. W. Norton and Co.Google Scholar
  29. von Hirsch, A. (1996). Extending the harm principle: ‘remote’ harms and fair imputation. In A. P. Simester & A. T. H. Smith (Eds.), Harm and culpability (pp. 258–274). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of St. GallenSt. GallenSwitzerland

Personalised recommendations