Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 175, Issue 3, pp 751–767 | Cite as

Predictive processing, perceiving and imagining: Is to perceive to imagine, or something close to it?

Article

Abstract

This paper examines the relationship between perceiving and imagining on the basis of predictive processing models in neuroscience. Contrary to the received view in philosophy of mind, which holds that perceiving and imagining are essentially distinct, these models depict perceiving and imagining as deeply unified and overlapping. It is argued that there are two mutually exclusive implications of taking perception and imagination to be fundamentally unified. The view defended is what I dub the ecological–enactive view given that it does not succumb to internalism about the mind-world relation, and allows one to keep a version of the received view in play.

Keywords

Predictive processing Imagination Perception Internalism Embodiment Enactivism Realization 

Notes

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by an Australian Research Council Discovery Project “Minds in Skilled Performance” (DP170102987), a John Templeton Foundation Grant “Probabilitizing Consciousness: Implications and New Directions”, by a Mind, Brain and Cognitive Evolution fellowship at Ruhr University Bochum, and by a John Templeton Foundation Academic Cross-Training Fellowship (ID #60708). The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation. Thanks to Julian Kiverstein, Jelle Bruineberg, Erik Rietveld, Micah Allen and Jon Opie for comments on a previous version of this paper. Thanks also to the audience members of the Acting Ahead of Actuality conference at the University of Dubrovnik, Croatia, 17-18 June 2016, and to the audience members of the Imagination and Representation workshop at Flinders University, Adelaide, 28 September 2015, for valuable suggestions for improvement. And finally thanks to an anonymous reviewer.

References

  1. Anderson, M., & Chemero, A. (2013). The problem with brain GUTs: Conflation of different senses of “prediction” threatens metaphysical disaster. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 204–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bar, M. (2007). The proactive brain: Using analogies and associations to generate predictions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(7), 280–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bruineberg, J., & Rietveld, E. (2014). Self-organization, free energy minimization, and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neurosciences. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00599.Google Scholar
  4. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Action, embodiment, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Clark, A. (2012). Dreaming the whole cat: Generative models, predictive processing, and the enactivist conception of perceptual experience. Mind, 121(483), 753–771.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Clark, A. (2013a). Expecting the world: Perception, prediction, and the origins of knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, CX(9), 469–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clark, A. (2013b). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 181–253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Clark, A. (2014). Perceiving as predicting. In D. Stokes, M. Matthen, & S. Biggs (Eds.), Perception and its modalities. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Clark, A. (2015). Radical predictive processing. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53, 3–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Clark, A. (forthcoming). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Downloaded from: http://www.researchgate.net/publication/287216594.
  13. Colombo, M., & Wright, C. (2016). Explanatory pluralism: An unrewarding prediction error for free energy theorists. Brain and Cognition. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2016.02.003.Google Scholar
  14. Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Friston, K. (2005). A theory of cortical responses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 360, 815–836.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: A rough guide to the brain? Cell Press. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.005.Google Scholar
  17. Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Friston, K. (2011). Embodied inference: Or ‘I Think Therefore I Am, If I Am What I Think’. In W. Tschacher & C. Bergomi (Eds.), The implications of embodiment (cognition and communication) (pp. 89–125). Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  19. Friston, K. (2013). Life as we know it. Journal of the Royal Society, Interface, 10, 20130475. doi: 10.1098/rsif.2013.0475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Friston, K., Adams, R., & Montague, R. (2012a). What is value-accumulated reward or evidence? Frontiers in Neurorobotics. doi: 10.3389/fnbot.2012.00011.Google Scholar
  21. Friston, K., & Stephan, K. E. (2007). Free energy and the brain. Synthese, 159, 417–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Friston, K., Thornton, C., & Clark, A. (2012b). Free-energy minimization and the dark-room problem. Frontiers in Psychology, 3(130), 1–7.Google Scholar
  23. Gallagher, S., Hutto, D. D., Slaby, J., & Cole, J. (2013). The brain as part of an enactive system. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(4), 421–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Gendler, T. (2011). Imagination. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1–32.Google Scholar
  25. Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. New York: Taylor & Francis.Google Scholar
  26. Hobson, J., & Friston, K. J. (2014). Consciousness, dreams, and inference: The Cartesian theatre revisited. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 21(1–2), 6–32.Google Scholar
  27. Hohwy, J. (2012). Attention and conscious perception in the hypothesis testing brain. Frontiers in Psychology. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00096.Google Scholar
  28. Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Hohwy, J. (2014). The self-evidencing brain. Nous. doi: 10.1111/nous.12062.Google Scholar
  30. Hohwy, J. (2015). The neural organ explains the mind. In T. Metzinger & J. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND, 19(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570016.Google Scholar
  31. Hohwy, J., Roepstorff, A., & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition, 108(33), 687–701.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015a). Extended cognition & the causal-constitutive fallacy: In search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 320–360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015b). Experiential fantasies, prediction and enactive minds. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22(3–4), 68–92.Google Scholar
  34. Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015c). Species of realization and the free energy principle. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(4), 706–723.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  38. Noë, A. (2009). Out of out heads. New York: Hill & Wang.Google Scholar
  39. O’Regan, K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–973.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Orlandi, N. (2014). The innocent eye: Why visio is not a cognitive process. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Paton, B., Skewes, J., Frith, C., & Hohwy, J. (2013). Skull-bound perception and precision optimization through culture. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(4), 222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Rescorla, M. (2013). Bayesian perceptual psychology. In M. Matthen (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of perception. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Roesptorff, A., Niewöhner, J., & Beck, S. (2010). Enculturating brains through patterned practices. Neural Networks, 23, 1051–1059.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Seth, A. K. (2014). A predictive processing theory of sensorimotor contingencies: Explaining the puzzle of perceptual presence and its absence in synesthesia. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2), 97–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Stevenson, L. (2003). Twelve concepts of imagination. British Journal of Aesthetics, 43(3), 238–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Stone, J. V. (2013). Bayes’ rule. Sheffield: Sebtel Press.Google Scholar
  47. Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Ward, D. (2012). Enjoying the spread: Conscious externalism reconsidered. Mind, 121(483), 731–752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of WollongongWollongongAustralia

Personalised recommendations