Skip to main content
Log in

Understanding: not know-how

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is considerable agreement among epistemologists that certain abilities are constitutive of understanding-why. These abilities include: constructing explanations, drawing conclusions, and answering questions. This agreement has led epistemologists to conclude that understanding is a kind of know-how. However, in this paper, I argue that the abilities constitutive of understanding are the same kind of cognitive abilities that we find in ordinary cases of knowledge-that and not the kind of practical abilities associated with know-how. I argue for this by disambiguating between different senses of abilities that are too often lumped together. As a consequence, non-reductionists about understanding—those that claim that understanding-why is not reducible to knowledge-that—need to find another way to motivate the view. In the end, the fact that abilities are constitutive of understanding-why does not give us reason to conclude that understanding is a kind of know-how.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A version of this case was introduced in Pritchard (2010). I simply changed the cause of the fire from faulty wiring to batteries sparking for the sake of variety and as a genuine public service announcement.

  2. Some, such as Sliwa (2015), claim that the daughter understands here, but she just has very limited understanding. Despite this, there is agreement that for the daughter to understand better would be for her to have additional knowledge—knowledge-how to give an explanation. This nuance will be developed in more detail in Sect. 2.

  3. The following endorse a reductive view of understanding: Lipton (2004), Kelp (2015), Khalifa (2013a, b), Riaz (2015), Sliwa (2015).

  4. The following endorse a non-reductive view of understanding: Elgin (2007), Grimm (2014), Hills (2016), Lawler (2016), Pritchard (2014), Riggs (2003).

  5. For example, Grimm (2017, especially n. 2) and Khalifa (2013b) claim objectual understanding is not different from understanding-why. See, Elgin (2007), Kelp (2015), Kvanvig (2003), Riggs (2003), Wilkenfeld (2013), and Zagzebski (2001) for more on the uniqueness of objectual understanding.

  6. Emphasis in original.

  7. The following endorse anti-intellectualism: Adams (2009), Carr (1981), Devitt (2011), Ryle (1949), Wallis (2008). The following endorse intellectualism: Pavese (2015), Stanley (2011), Stanley and Williamson (2001).

  8. The following endorse a virtue theoretical approach to the nature of knowledge: Baehr (2006), Greco (2009, 2010), Pritchard (2010), Riggs (2009), Sosa (2009, 2015), Zagzebski (1996). There is an interesting debate within virtue epistemology whether or not epistemic virtues are best understood as character traits (Baehr 2006; Zagzebski 1996) or processes and powers of the mind (Greco 2010; Sosa 2015). For the purposes of this paper I focus on the view that epistemic virtues are powers and processes of the mind.

  9. The scope of the conditions under which one must get things right in order to have an ability is determined by the particular domain, subject matter, or practical context.

  10. Not only does Sosa discuss an triple-S structure of competency more generally, he also discusses epistemic norms through an AAA (triple-A) structure. For the purposes of this paper, we can discuss the general themes about ability using theory neutral language to broaden the lessons beyond Sosa’s view and perhaps even beyond virtue epistemology itself.

  11. The lines between ability functional and ability judgmental are blurry. Since I am arguing that both are constitutive of propositional knowledge, the precise line does not matter for our purposes.

  12. There is dispute over the way in which dispositions contribute to the nature of know-how. For an in-depth discussion on the difference between intellectualists and anti-intellectualists on the way dispositions contribute to know-how see Bengson and Moffett (2012). Despite this, it is enough for our purposes to stick with the dispositional approach adopted by virtue epistemologists.

  13. See Pavese (2015) for a discussion on the way that know-how is uniquely about practical tasks and for an account of practical sense.

  14. There is an objection to the first two abilities that Hills (2016) discusses. The objection is that one may not have any linguistic abilities and still have understanding. I think this objection is on track. After all, one can have knowledge without having any linguistic abilities to give a verbal answer to a “whether p” question. For simplicity’s sake I focus on cases in which agents already have an ordinary set of abilities, including linguistic.

  15. This may bring to mind Sosa’s triple-S and triple-A structure of competences. To have an innermost skill is to reliably get things right in a set of shapes and situations. My claim here is that if someone has an ability in one situation, then the person will also have the ability in a similarly relevant situation. For example, since I know how to drive, the exact road I am on, be it the BQE or the New Jersey Turnpike, I will still get on driving just as well. In the epistemic case, if I have the ability to see that the fire is caused by a particular battery in one house, I can make judgments about another house, or even concerning different battery types.

  16. See Sect. 3.3.

  17. For example, Hetherington (2006) argues for such a view.

References

  • Adams, M. (2009). Empirical evidence and the knowledge-that/knowledge-how distinction. Synthese, 170(1), 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, J. (2006). Character, reliability and virtue epistemology. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(223), 193–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. (2012). Nonpropositional intellectualism. In J. Bengson & M. A. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 161–195). Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1981). Knowledge in practice. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18(1), 53–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A., & Pritchard, D. (2015). Knowledge-how and cognitive achievement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(1), 181–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2011). Methodology and the nature of knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy, 108(4), 205–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2007). Understanding and the facts. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2009). Knowledge and success from ability. Philosophical Studies, 142(1), 17–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2014). Understanding as knowledge of causes. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue epistemology naturalized: Bridges between virtue epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 329–345). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2017). Understanding and transparency. In S. Grimm, C. Baumberger & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New essays in epistemology and the philosophy of science (pp. 212–229). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2006). How to know (that knowledge-that is knowledge- how). In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology futures (pp. 71–94). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2016). Understanding why. Nous, 50(4), 661–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2015). Understanding phenomena. Synthese, 192(12), 3799–3816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2013a). The role of explanation in understanding. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64(1), 161–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2013b). Is understanding explanatory or objectual? Synthese, 190(6), 1153–1171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2009). Knowledge and credit. Philosophical Studies, 142(1), 27–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, I. (2016). Reductionism about understanding why. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 116(2), 229–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2015). Practical senses. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(29), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2010). The nature and value of knowledge: Three investigations (with Adrian Haddock and Alan Millar). Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2014). Knowledge and understanding. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue epistemology naturalized: Bridges between virtue epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 315–327). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riaz, A. (2015). Moral understanding and moral knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 172(1), 113–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, W. (2003). Understanding ‘virtue’ and the virtue of understanding. In M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski (Eds.), Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology (pp. 203–227). Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, W. (2009). Two problems of easy credit. Synthese, 169(1), 201–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sliwa, P. (2015). Understanding and knowing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 115(1), 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2009). Reflective knowledge: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. II). Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and agency. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know-how. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallis, C. (2008). Consciousness, context, and know-how. Synthese, 160(1), 123–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190(6), 997–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind. Cambridge: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2001). Recovering understanding. In M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty: Essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the anonymous referee for very helpful comments and suggestions. For many other helpful comments and conversations, I would like to thank Nathan Ballantyne, Stephen Grimm, Diana Heney, Sam Kampa, Insa Lawler, Michael Strevens, Peter Siepel, Coran Stewart, and special thanks to John Mumm.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emily Sullivan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sullivan, E. Understanding: not know-how. Philos Stud 175, 221–240 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0863-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0863-z

Keywords

Navigation