Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 174, Issue 11, pp 2845–2869 | Cite as

Defeaters to best interests reasoning in genetic enhancement

Article
  • 334 Downloads

Abstract

Pre-natal genetic enhancement affords us unprecedented capacity to shape our skills, talents, appearance and perhaps subsequently the quality of our lives in terms of overall happiness, success and wellbeing. Despite its powerful appeal, some have raised important and equally persuasive concerns against genetic enhancement. Sandel has argued that compassion and humility, themselves grounded in the unpredictability of talents and skills, would be lost. Habermas has argued that genetically altered individuals will see their lives as dictated by their parents’ design and therefore will not acquire an appropriate self-understanding. How should we view enhancement efforts in light of these concerns? I propose that we begin by adopting a defeasibility stance. That is, I ask whether our belief that genetic enhancements serve in the best interests of the child is reason to genetically enhance, underscoring a sort of epistemic vulnerability. I utilize the epistemological notions of defeasible reasons, undercutting (also called undermining) and overriding (or rebutting) defeaters in order to better understand and systematically evaluate the force of such concerns. I argue that close examination of both objections using this framework shows that we have reason to enhance, a reason that is defeasible but as yet, undefeated.

Keywords

Genetic enhancement Undercutting defeaters Overriding defeaters Sandel Habermas Savulescu 

References

  1. Asch, A., & David, W. (2012). Selecting for disability: Acceptable lives, acceptable reasons. The American Journal of Bioethics, 12(8), 30–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bostrom, N. (2003). Human genetic enhancements: A transhumanist perspective. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 27, 493–506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Brock, D. (2009). Is selection of children wrong. In J. Savulescu & N. Bostrom (Eds.), Human enhancement (pp. 251–276). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Buchanan, A., Brock, D., Daniels, N., & Wikler, D. (2000). From chance to choice: Genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Caspi, A., McClay, J., et al. (2002). Role of genotype in the cycle of violence in maltreated children. Science, 297(5582), 851–854.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Caspi, A., Sugdeon, K., et al. (2003). Influence of life stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism in the 5-HTT gene. Science, 301(5631), 386–389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Casullo, A. (2003). A priori justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Childress, T. L., & Beauchamp, T. L. (2013). Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Daniels, N. (2009). Can anyone really be talking about ethically modifying human nature. In J. Savulescu & N. Bostrom (Eds.), Human Enhancement (pp. 25–42). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Davis, D. (2010). Genetic dilemmas: Reproductive technology, parental choices and children’s futures. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Dennis, C. (2003). Altered states. Nature, 421, 686–688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Feinberg, J. (1980). The child’s right to an open future. In W. Aiken & H. Lafolette (Eds.), Whose child? children’s rights, parental authority, and state power. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  13. Gazzinga, M. (2005). The ethical brain. New York: Harper Perennial.Google Scholar
  14. Habermas, J. (2003). The future of human nature. Malden: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  15. Hyman, S. (2006). Using genetics to understand human behavior. In E. Parens, A. R. Chapman & N. Press (Eds.), Wrestling with behavioral genetics (pp. 109–127). Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Janvid, M. (2008). Defeaters and rising standards of justification. Acta Analytica, 23(1), 45–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Juth, N. (2011). Enhancement, autonomy and authenticity. In J. Savulescu, R. ter Meulen, & G. Kahane (Eds.), Enhancing human capacities (pp. 34–48). Malden: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  18. Little, M. O. (1998). Cosmetic surgery, suspect norms and the ethics of complicity. In E. Parens (Ed.), Enhancing human traits (pp. 162–176). Washington: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Mehlman, M., & Botkins, J. (1998). Access to the genome: The challenge to equality. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Melis, G. (2014). Understanding undermining defeat. Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 433–442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Miko, I. (2008). Epistasis: Gene interaction and phenotype effects. Nature Education, 1(1), 197.Google Scholar
  22. Parens, E. (1998). Enhancing human traits. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Parens, E. (2004). Special supplement: Genetic differences and human identitities: On why talking about behavioral genetics is important and difficult. The Hastings Center Report, 34(1), S1–S36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Plantinga, A. (2000). Warranted christian belief. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Pollock, J. (1970). The structure of epistemic justification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 62–78.Google Scholar
  26. Resnick, D. B., & Vorhous, D. B. (2006). Genetic modification and genetic determinism. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 1, 9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Rothenfluch, S. (2016). A subjectivist solution to the problem of harm in genetic enhancement. Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics, 3(4), 113–130.Google Scholar
  28. Sandel, M. (2007). The case against perfection. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Savulescu, J. (2001). Procreative beneficence: Why we should select the best children. Bioethics, 15(5/6), 413–426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Savulescu, J. (2007). Genetic interventions and the ethics of enhancement of human beings. In B. Steinbock (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of bioethics (pp. 516–535). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Savulescu, J., & Kahane, G. (2009). The moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life. Bioethics, 23(5), 274–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Schaffner, K. (2006). Behavior: Its nature and nurture. In E. Parens, A. Chapman & N. Press (Eds.), Wrestling with Human Nature (pp. 3–73). Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Singer, P. (2009). Parental Choice and Human Improvement. In J. Savulescu & N. Bostrom (Eds.), Human Enhancement (pp. 277–289). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Steup, M. (1996). An introduction to contemporary epistemology. Upper Saddle River: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  35. Sturgeon, S. (2012). Pollock on defeasible reasons. Philosophical Studies, 1(1), 1–14.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of PortlandPortlandUSA

Personalised recommendations