Abstract
This note responds to criticism put forth by Jessica Keiser against a theory of lying as Stalnakerian assertion. According to this account, to lie is to say something one believes to be false and thereby propose that it become common ground. Keiser objects that this view wrongly counts particular kinds of non-literal speech as instances of lying. In particular, Keiser argues that the view invariably counts metaphors and certain uses of definite descriptions as lies. It is argued here that both these claims are false.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
See Stokke (2013). Keiser (2016, Sect. 5.2) who summarizes the common ground view of assertion as the claim that “S asserts p iff in stating p S proposes to add p to the common ground.” This is a stronger view of assertion than the one employed in my account of lying, i.e., the view given by (A1)–(A2). However, I want to show that, even ignoring this, my view does not have the undesirable consequences Keiser points to.
The main reason for this is the desiredatum to count as genuine lies cases of lying without the intent to deceive, so called “bald-faced lies.” See Stokke (2013) for discussion.
See Stalnaker (2002, p. 716).
The fact that metaphorical meaning survives embeddings—as in this case, under attitudes—is one major piece of evidence against the Gricean view of metaphors as cases of (particularized) conversational implicatures. As noted, if the Gricean view is wrong, my view of lying has an even easier time not counting all metaphorical utterances as lies.
On a Russellian view of definite descriptions, an utterance of “the man drinking a martini” asserts that there is a unique (salient) man drinking a martini. Hence, on such a view, it is harder to avoid the result that all utterances like Alice's utterance of (5) are lies. However, I take it that there are sufficient, independent reasons for rejecting a Russellian view of definite descriptions in favor of a presuppositional view. For recent discussion, see, e.g., Heim and Kratzer (1998), Elbourne (2005, 2010), Schoubye (2009, 2013), Glanzberg (2007), Kripke (2005).
References
Bach, K. (2001). You don’t say? Synthese, 128, 15–44.
Bezuidenhout, A. (2001). Metaphor and what is said. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25, 156–186.
Camp, E. (2012). Sarcasm, pretense, and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Noûs, 46(4), 587–634.
Donnellan, K. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75, 281–304.
Elbourne, P. (2005). Situations and individuals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Elbourne, P. (2010). The existence entailments of definite descriptions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 33(1), 1–10.
Fallis, D. (2014). Review of Lying, misleading, and what is said: An exploration in philosophy of language and in ethics, by Jennifer Mather Saul. European Journal of Philosophy, 22(S1), e17–e22.
Glanzberg, M. (2007). Definite descriptions and quantifier scope: Some Mates cases reconsidered. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 3(2), 133–158.
Grice, H. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.
Keiser, J. (2016). Bald-faced lies: How to make a move in a language game without making a move in a conversation. Philosophical Studies, 173, 461–477.
Kripke, S. (2005). Russell’s notion of scope. Mind, 114(456), 1005–1037.
Neale, S. (1992). Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15, 509–559.
Saul, J. (2012). Lying, misleading, and what is said: An exploration in philosophy of language and in ethics. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Schoubye, A. (2009). Descriptions, truth value intuitions, and questions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 32, 583–617.
Schoubye, A. (2013). Ghosts, murderers, and the semantics of descriptions. Noûs, 47(3), 496–533.
Schoubye, A. J., & Stokke, A. (2015). What is said? Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12133.
Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1981). Irony and the use-mention distinction. In P. Cole (Ed.), Radical pragmatics (pp. 295–318). New York: Academic Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1999 [1970]). Pragmatics. In Context and content (pp. 31–46). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1999 [1974]). Pragmatic presuppositions. In Context and content (pp. 47–62). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1999 [1978]). Assertion. In Context and content (pp. 78–95). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1999 [1998]). On the representation of context. In Context and content (pp. 96–114). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Stalnaker, R. (2002). Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 701–721.
Stalnaker, R. (2014). Context. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Stern, J. (2000). Metaphor in context. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Stokke, A. (2013). Lying and asserting. Journal of Philosophy, CX(1), 33–60.
Stokke, A. (2016). Lying and misleading in discourse. Philosophical Review, 125(1), 83–134.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to Don Fallis for helpful comments and suggestions.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Stokke, A. Metaphors and Martinis: a response to Jessica Keiser. Philos Stud 174, 853–859 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0709-0
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0709-0